Ses 6save More Tomorrow
Ses 6save More Tomorrow
Richard H. Thaler
University of Chicago
Shlomo Benartzi
University of California, Los Angeles
We are grateful to Brian Tarbox for implementing the Save More Tomorrow娂 plan and
for sharing the data with us. We would also like to thank many people at the following
companies for their help: Financial Engines, Hewitt Associates, Ispat Inland, John Hancock,
Philips Electronics, and the Vanguard Group. Jodi Dicenzo, Bill Sharpe, and Steve Utkus
deserve special thanks. We are also grateful for comments from David Laibson, Brigitte
Madrian, Casey Mulligan, Ted O’Donoghue, and Cass Sunstein. Benartzi would like to
thank Reish Luftman McDaniel & Reicher for financial support. Save More Tomorrow is
a registered trademark of Benartzi and Thaler, but the plan is available at no charge to
any company that is willing to share data on the outcomes. This paper is dedicated to
Sherwin Rosen, Thaler’s thesis advisor. Thaler would not be an economist today if not
for Rosen’s help. The usual disclaimer, assigning none of the blame for errors to those
thanked above, applies in spades to Sherwin. He would not have liked this paper much,
but we sure would have enjoyed hearing him complain about it!
S164
behavioral economics S165
been in place for four annual raises, are as follows: (1) a high pro-
portion (78 percent) of those offered the plan joined, (2) the vast
majority of those enrolled in the SMarT plan (80 percent) remained
in it through the fourth pay raise, and (3) the average saving rates
for SMarT program participants increased from 3.5 percent to 13.6
percent over the course of 40 months. The results suggest that be-
havioral economics can be used to design effective prescriptive pro-
grams for important economic decisions.
I. Introduction
1
It is sometimes argued that this fact can be explained by selection effects, i.e., that
those workers with a “taste for savings” go to work for companies with more attractive
pension benefits. But it is important not to push this argument too far. It is implausible
that pension benefits are so salient and important that workers sort themselves to firms
primarily on this basis. Many other features of a job determine its attractiveness, and
potential employees must make trade-offs. To give one example, one of the authors of
this paper is much more interested in collegiate athletics than the other, but he teaches
at the University of Chicago, not UCLA! Therefore, we should not expect underlying
preferences and employment characteristics to be perfectly correlated on any single
dimension.
behavioral economics S167
savings in which self-control and mental accounting play key roles. Fi-
nally, prescriptive theories are attempts to offer advice on how people
can improve their decision making and get closer to the normative ideal.
Prescriptions often have a second-best quality. For a golfer who hits a
slice (in which the ball tails off to the right) when he would prefer to
hit the ball straight, simple prescriptive advice might be to aim to the
left. Better prescriptive advice would help the golfer hit the ball straight.
This paper is an attempt at good prescriptive savings advice.
Before writing a prescription, one must know the symptoms of the
disease being treated. Households may save less than the life cycle rate
for various reasons. First, determining the appropriate savings rate is
difficult, even for someone with economics training. Since the switch
from defined-benefit to defined-contribution savings plans is recent,
there are as yet no satisfactory heuristics that approximate a good so-
lution to the problem.2 One obvious solution to this problem is financial
education (Bernheim, Garrett, and Maki 1997). Second, saving for re-
tirement requires self-control. When surveyed about their low savings
rates, many households report that they would like to save more but
lack the willpower. For example, Choi et al. (in press) report that two-
thirds of their sample of 401(k) participants think that their savings rate
is “too low.”3 A third problem, closely related to self-control, is pro-
crastination, the familiar tendency to postpone unpleasant tasks. In Choi
et al.’s group of self-reported undersavers, 35 percent express an inten-
tion to increase their savings rate in the next few months, but 86 percent
of these well-intended savers have made no changes to their plan four
months later.
Self-control and procrastination used to be strange concepts to econ-
omists but are now topics of growing interest to behavioral economics
theorists (e.g., Laibson 1997; O’Donoghue and Rabin 1999). Modern
models of these problems use the concept of hyperbolic discounting
(see Ainslie 1975). Since Strotz’s (1955) early paper, economists have
known that intertemporal choices are time consistent only if agents
discount exponentially using a discount rate that is constant over time.
But there is considerable evidence that people display time-inconsistent
behavior, specifically, weighing current and near-term consumption es-
pecially heavily. Consider a choice between two rewards, a small one at
time t (St) and a big one at time t ⫹ 1 (Bt⫹1). When t is far off, agents
prefer Bt⫹1, since the difference in the value of the prizes exceeds the
perceived costs of waiting. But as t approaches zero, the ratio of dis-
2
The most common heuristics in place appear to be to save the maximum allowed by
law or to save the minimum necessary to receive the full “match” offered by the employer.
Neither of these amounts was computed to be a solution to the life cycle savings problem.
3
Similarly, a 1997 survey by Public Agenda finds that 76 percent of respondents think
that they should be saving more for retirement. See Farkus and Johnson (1997) for details.
S168 journal of political economy
counted values increases, causing people to switch their preferences.4
Such present-biased preferences can be captured with models that em-
ploy hyperbolic discounting. These models come in two varieties: so-
phisticated and naive. Sophisticated agents (modeled by Laibson) re-
alize that they have hyperbolic preferences and take steps to deal with
the problem, whereas naive agents fail to appreciate at least the extent
of their problem (see O’Donoghue and Rabin 1999, 2001). Actual be-
havior is likely best described by something between naivete and
sophistication.
Hyperbolic agents procrastinate because they (wrongly) think that
whatever they will be doing later will not be as important as what they
are doing now. The more naive agents are, the more pronounced the
tendency to procrastinate. Procrastination, in turn, produces a strong
tendency toward inertia, or what Samuelson and Zeckhauser (1988)
have dubbed status quo bias. Status quo bias is prevalent in the retire-
ment savings domain. For example, Samuelson and Zeckhauser report
on the behavior of the 1987 participants of TIAA-CREF, the large re-
tirement plan that then catered to university employees. Their analysis
reveals that the median number of changes in the asset allocation over
the lifetime was zero! In other words, more than half the participants in
TIAA-CREF reached retirement with the same asset allocation as the
day they became eligible for the plan. Note that zero changes means
that participants were electing a constant flow into the two funds then
offered, TIAA, a fixed-income fund, and CREF, a stock fund, and en-
gaged in no rebalancing. Since stocks appreciated much more than
bonds over this period, participants with a constant flow (such as 50–
50, the most common allocation) ended up with a much larger share
in stocks over time. A recent study by Ameriks and Zeldes (2000), using
a 10-year panel of TIAA-CREF participants, finds a similar result. Nearly
half of the participants made no changes to their plan over the 10-year
period.5
The importance of procrastination and status quo bias in the design
of prescriptive savings plans is illustrated by the experience some firms
have had with so-called automatic enrollment plans. In such plans, when
employees first become eligible for the savings plan, they are automat-
ically enrolled unless they explicitly opt out. So, unlike the typical plan,
in which the default is not to join, here the default is to join. Employees
4
For evidence on hyperbolic discounting, see Thaler (1981) and the papers in Loew-
enstein and Elster (1992).
5
Choi, Laibson, and Mettrick (2000) find somewhat more frequent trading in a sample
of workers at two firms in 1998 and 1999, partly because of the ease of trading via the
Internet that was possible at both firms. But this increase in trading may also be attributable
to rapidly rising stock prices during this period and the resulting excitement among
individual investors.
behavioral economics S169
who take no action are typically enrolled at a modest saving rate (such
as 3 percent) and a conservative investment strategy. Standard economic
theory would predict that this change would have virtually no effect on
saving behavior. The costs of actively joining the plan (typically filling
out a short form) are trivial compared with the potential benefits of the
tax-free accumulation of wealth, and in some cases a “match” is provided
by the employer, in which the employer typically contributes 50 cents
to the plan for every dollar the employee contributes, up to some max-
imum. In contrast, if agents display procrastination and status quo bias,
then automatic enrollment could be useful in increasing participation
rates.
Consistent with the behavioral predictions, automatic enrollment
plans have proved to be remarkably successful in increasing enrollments.
In one plan studied by Madrian and Shea (1999), participation rates
for newly eligible workers increased from 49 percent to 86 percent.
Other plans have obtained participation rates of over 90 percent (Choi
et al., in press). But there is a downside to automatic enrollment. The
very inertia that explains why automatic enrollment increases partici-
pation rates can also lower the saving rates of those who do participate.
In the firm Madrian and Shea studied, the vast majority of new enrollees
elected the default saving rate (3 percent), and Madrian and Shea’s
analysis shows that many of these employees would have elected a higher
saving rate if left to their own devices (see Choi et al. [in press], who
explore these issues in depth). A goal of the SMarT plan is to obtain
some of the advantages of automatic enrollment while avoiding some
of the disadvantages.
On the basis of our analysis of undersaving households in the previous
section, some elements of a proposed solution are fairly obvious. The
presence of bounded rationality suggests that the program should be
simple and should help people approximate the life cycle saving rate
if they are unable to do so themselves. Hyperbolic discounting implies
that opportunities to save more in the future will be considered more
attractive than those in the present. Procrastination and inertia suggest
that once employees are enrolled in the program, they should remain
in until they opt out.
The final behavioral factor that should be considered in designing a
prescriptive savings plan is loss aversion, the empirically demonstrated
tendency for people to weigh losses significantly more heavily than gains.
Estimates of loss aversion are typically close to 2.0: losses hurt roughly
twice as much as gains yield pleasure. These estimates come both from
risky choice (Tversky and Kahneman 1992) and from riskless choice
(Kahneman, Knetsch, and Thaler 1990).
Loss aversion affects savings because once households get used to a
particular level of disposable income, they tend to view reductions in
S170 journal of political economy
that level as a loss. Thus households may be reluctant to increase their
contributions to the savings plan because they do not want to experience
this cut in take-home pay. Significantly, gains and losses appear to be
experienced in nominal dollars. For example, in a study of perceptions
of fairness (Kahneman et al. 1986), subjects were asked to judge the
fairness of pay cuts and pay increases in a company located in a com-
munity with substantial unemployment. One group of subjects was told
that there was no inflation in the community and was asked whether a
7 percent wage cut was “fair.” A majority, 62 percent, judged the action
to be unfair. Another group was told that there was 12 percent inflation
and was asked to judge the perceived fairness of a 5 percent raise. Here,
only 22 percent thought the action was unfair. Similar results suggesting
this money illusion are reported by Shafir, Diamond, and Tversky
(1997). The combination of loss aversion and money illusion suggests
that pay increases may provide a propitious time to try to get workers
to save more, since they are less likely to consider an increased contri-
bution to the plan as a loss than they would at other times of the year.
In summary, for households that appear to be saving too little, the
behavioral analysis stresses four factors that are important explanatory
factors: bounded rationality, self-control, procrastination (which pro-
duces inertia), and nominal loss aversion. These households are not
sure how much they should be saving, though they realize that it is
probably more than they are doing now; but they procrastinate about
saving more now, thinking that they will get to it later. Our program to
increase saving is aimed at these households.
6
The intuition here is the same as one in which requests to give a talk or write a chapter
meet with more success when they are received many months ahead of time.
behavioral economics S171
people in the plan. Fourth, the employee can opt out of the plan at
any time. Although we expect few employees to be unhappy with the
plan, it is important that they can always opt out. Knowledge of this
feature will also make employees more comfortable about joining.
The SMarT plan has many features that were included with the in-
tention of making it attractive to employees who want to save more. It
is not possible to say on theoretical grounds which features are most
important, nor can theory tell us the ideal levels to select for many of
the parameters that must be picked (e.g., the delay between the solic-
itation letter and the start of the program, the rate of increase, and the
methods of soliciting and educating potential participants). Similarly,
we cannot say a priori whether particular features, such as linking the
increases in the savings rate to pay increases, are just one of many
attractive components or are essential ingredients to success. We shall
learn more about these questions over time as firms adopt the plan and
provide data for analysis.
At this time we have three implementations on which we can report,
each done rather differently. The particular design features were gen-
erally not selected by us but, rather, reflect the preferences of the firms
that have adopted the plan. In this type of field research, we, the aca-
demic investigators, have quite limited control over many of the details,
especially if compared with a laboratory environment. Nevertheless, it
is not possible to study actual household savings behavior in a lab, so
we are grateful for the data we are able to report here.
In most cases with rank and file workers, the computer pro-
gram calculates that workers contribute the maximum [allowed
by the Internal Revenue Service (IRS) and the plan rules] and
makes that recommendation. As a practical matter, when the
average worker receives this recommendation from the com-
puter program or the “financial planner,” s/he shuts down and
does nothing. So in all cases, after we reviewed their current
plan but before I hit the “Get Advice” button, I would discuss
willingness to save with each participant. As you can imagine,
the majority of workers live paycheck to paycheck and can
barely make ends meet, and they tell you that immediately. …
If a participant indicated a willingness to immediately increase
their deferral level by more than 5 percent, I hit the “Get
Advice” button. Otherwise, I would constrain the advice pro-
posed to an increase of no more than 5 percent. [Personal
communication from Brian Tarbox, the investment consultant]
7
Here and elsewhere, when we refer to a five-percentage-point increase, we are referring
to an increase of percentage points, e.g., from a 2 percent saving rate to a 7 percent saving
rate.
behavioral economics S173
TABLE 1
Participation Data for the First Implementation of
SMarT
TABLE 2
Average Saving Rates (%) for the First Implementation of SMarT
Participants Participants
Who Did Not Who Accepted Participants Participants
Contact the the Consultant’s Who Joined Who Declined
Financial Recommended the SMarT the SMarT
Consultant Saving Rate Plan Plan All
Participants
initially
choosing
each
option* 29 79 162 45 315
Pre-advice 6.6 4.4 3.5 6.1 4.4
First pay raise 6.5 9.1 6.5 6.3 7.1
Second pay
raise 6.8 8.9 9.4 6.2 8.6
Third pay raise 6.6 8.7 11.6 6.1 9.8
Fourth pay
raise 6.2 8.8 13.6 5.9 10.6
* There is attrition from each group over time. The number of employees who remain by the time of the fourth
pay raise is 229.
the investment consultant was brought into the company, the overall
savings rate in the plan was 4.4 percent. The employees who did not
want to talk to the consultant were saving more than the average, 6.6
percent. The group that accepted the advice of the consultant had been
saving at exactly the overall company average, 4.4 percent, and after
implementing the advice, they began saving 9.1 percent of their salary.
At the end of our data collection period, that rate had slipped slightly
to 8.8 percent. Those who were unwilling to accept the advice were, not
surprisingly, starting from a lower base of 3.5 percent and so would find
the advice harder to adopt. Once they got their first pay raise, however,
their saving rate jumped to 6.5 percent, and after three more raises, it
was up 13.6 percent. Those participating in the SMarT plan ended up
with a much higher saving rate than those who accepted the consultant’s
recommendation.
Of course, the implementation of the SMarT plan was not conducted
as an experiment with random assignment to conditions. Participants
selected themselves into the SMarT plan. In other circumstances, one
might worry that the observed increase in savings rates might be attrib-
utable to some unmeasured “taste for saving” in the households that
joined the SMarT plan; however, this worry seems unwarranted here on
two counts. First, the SMarT participants had been saving very little
before joining the plan, so one would have to believe that their taste
for saving was newly acquired. Second, recall that the SMarT plan was
offered only to those employees who were unwilling to increase their
savings rate immediately by 5 percent. So, if anything, the group that
behavioral economics S175
accepted the consultant’s advice would appear to have a greater taste
for saving than those in the SMarT plan.
The design of the study also rules out an information-based expla-
nation for our results. Since the employees met with the investment
consultant, they received useful information about proper savings rates,
and this information quite possibly could affect their savings rates. All
the employees who agreed to meet with the consultant received this
information, however, including those who accepted the consultant’s
advice to increase their savings rate immediately. We find it difficult to
construct an information-based explanation for the subsequent in-
creases in savings rates for those enrolled in the SMarT plan.
TABLE 3
Average Saving Rates for Ispat Inland (%)
tributing factor. Those who were not in the plan might have ignored
the letter altogether. The letter came with the heading “important in-
formation about your 401(k) account,” a teaser that would not be of
particular interest to employees who were not in the plan.
The immediate effect on savings was about what might be expected.
Those joining SMarT increased their saving rates by roughly 2 percent,
whereas those not joining the program did not change their saving rates
much. If the experience in the first implementation is repeated here
and few employees drop out of the SMarT plan, then saving rates will
continue to increase whenever the employees get raises.
11
Division A is now closing down, so the long-term results of the SMarT plan will not
be available.
12
There are pros and cons to offering this choice to participants, as opposed to just
picking a single rate of increase. The obvious advantage is that employees can select the
rate of increase they like best. The disadvantage is that simply being forced to make such
a choice adds another layer of complexity that could discourage some potential enrollees.
We included the default 2 percent rate of increase with the goal of mitigating this potential
impediment to enrolling. Only a controlled experiment will be able to determine whether
the pros of offering choice outweigh the cons.
S178 journal of political economy
TABLE 4
Average Saving Rates (%) for Philips Electronics
Employees Who
Were Already Employees Who
Saving in Were Not Saving
December 2001 in December 2001
Joined Did Not Joined Did Not All
Date SMarT Join SMarT SMarT Join SMarT Employees
A. Control Group
Observations 7,405 7,053 14,458
Pre-SMarT (December
2001) 5.65 .00 2.90
Post-SMarT (March 2002) 5.76 .70 3.29
B. Test Group (Divisions A and O Combined)
Observations 180 339 36 260 815
Pre-SMarT (December
2001) 5.26 5.38 .00 .00 3.40
Post-SMarT (March 2002) 6.83 5.72 5.03 1.55 4.61
C. Division A
Observations 66 190 10 163 449
Pre-SMarT (December
2001) 5.47 5.48 .00 .00 3.12
Post-SMarT (March 2002) 7.32 5.97 6.80 1.54 4.38
D. Division O
Observations 114 149 26 77 366
Pre-SMarT (December
2001) 5.14 5.25 .00 .00 3.74
Post-SMarT (March 2002) 6.55 5.41 4.35 1.58 4.89
Note.—The “test” group consists of individuals at Divisions A and O.
grammed increase among those already saving). The savings rate went
up more dramatically for those employees who simultaneously enrolled
in the 401(k) and SMarT. Interestingly, there also seemed to be a spill-
over effect on those who did not join the SMarT plan. In the two ex-
perimental divisions in which SMarT was introduced, even those em-
ployees who did not join SMarT increased their savings rates more than
was observed in the control group.13
At the time of this writing (summer 2003), the second raise has oc-
curred in Division O, and we have some preliminary data on attrition
rates from the SMarT program. Of those who originally joined the pro-
gram, 13.5 percent have left Philips because they either quit or were
terminated. Of those remaining in the plan, eight employees (5.4 per-
cent of the original participants, 6.2 percent of those still working at
Philips) dropped out before the second raise, but another five em-
13
This pattern is consistent with evidence by Duflo and Saez (2000) on peer effects.
behavioral economics S179
ployees joined the plan. This experience of low dropout rates is com-
parable to that in the first implementation and suggests that, over time,
savings rates will continue to rise.
In this implementation, we were given access to some demographic
information about the employees as well as information about how the
plan was administered in each division. The participation rates in SMarT
were quite different in the two divisions, as shown in table 5. In Division
A, only 16.9 percent of the division’s employees joined the program
(76/449), whereas Division O had a take-up rate of 38.3 percent
(140/366). One potential explanation for this difference is that the
employees at Division O had the opportunity to meet with a certified
financial planner. In fact, 41.8 percent of the employees at Division O
met with the financial planner, and 81 percent of those who attended
such a meeting actually joined SMarT. Of course, electing to meet with
the planner might by itself signal a desire to save, so it is not possible
to ascertain the incremental effect of the financial planner on either
saving rates or SMarT participation.
Table 5 also provides some basic information on who joins the SMarT
plan. Neither gender nor age appears to be an important determining
factor. Employees with four to five years of tenure working for Philips
were the most likely to join, as were those with annual incomes of less
than $50,000.
At this stage, there are some preliminary lessons that can be drawn
from the Philips experience. First, the SMarT design feature linking
savings increases to pay increases, while desirable, may not be essential.
This is important, since some firms find it difficult to coordinate the
savings plan with the salary increases. Second, one-on-one meetings with
a financial planner appear to be a very effective (though costly) re-
cruitment tool, though selection problems make it difficult to parse out
the precise value of this intervention.
14
One might think that a 100 percent replacement rate would be too high, suggesting
that agents are very patient. However, survey evidence suggests that households desire an
increasing consumption profile. Laibson (1999) offers a cogent discussion of this issue
and reports that economists also prefer rising profiles for themselves. If agents want a
rising profile, then even a 100 percent replacement rate may be too low.
S182 journal of political economy
TABLE 6
Median Income Replacement Ratios (%)
Age
Income 25 35 45 55
A. Pre-SMarT
$25,000 57 57 56 55
$50,000 51 51 51 54
$75,000 48 49 46 43
B. Post-SMarT
$25,000 108 90 75 63
$50,000 98 83 70 62
$75,000 90 77 63 50
Note.—The table displays the median income replacement ratios for different
age and income profiles, using investment advice software by Financial Engines. The
projections are based on the following assumptions: no defined-benefit pension,
statutory social security benefits, employee saving rate of 4 percent before SMarT
and 14 percent thereafter, employer match of 50 cents on the dollar up to 6 percent,
portfolio mix of 60 percent stocks and 40 percent bonds, and retirement age of 65.
43 and 57 percent. Replacement rates are highest for the $25,000 in-
come category because social security offers substantial replacement at
that level. Panel B shows that replacement income rates are considerably
higher with the SMarT plan, especially for those joining the plan when
young. Obviously, increasing the savings rate is less effective when one
starts at 55 than at 25. Still, expected replacement rates exceed 100
percent in just one cell (108 percent replacement for those making
$25,000 per year who join the plan at age 25), so there does not appear
to be evidence that we have induced people to save too much. Fur-
thermore, if the stock market returns are exceptionally high, workers
nearing retirement can always reduce savings rates or plan an earlier
retirement if they have higher retirement benefits than they expected.
TABLE 7
Projected Saving Rates (%)
VI. Conclusions
The initial experience with the SMarT plan has been quite successful.
Many of the people who were offered the plan elected to use it, and a
majority of the people who joined the SMarT plan stuck with it. Con-
sequently, in the first implementation, for which we have data for four
annual raises, SMarT participants almost quadrupled their saving rates.
Of course, one reason why the SMarT plan works so well is that inertia
is so powerful. Once people enroll in the plan, few opt out. The SMarT
plan takes precisely the same behavioral tendency that induces people
to postpone saving indefinitely (i.e., procrastination and inertia) and
puts it to use. As the financial consultant involved in the first imple-
mentation has noted, in hindsight it would have been better to offer
the SMarT plan to all participants, even those who were willing to make
their initial savings increase more than the first step of the SMarT plan.
Very few of these eager savers ever got around to changing their savings
allocations again, whereas the SMarT plan participants were already
saving more than they were after just 16 months (see table 2)
Some economists have criticized practices such as automatic enroll-
ment and the SMarT plan on the grounds that they are paternalistic, a
term that is not meant to be complimentary. We agree that these plans
are paternalistic, but since no coercion is involved, they constitute what
Sunstein and Thaler (2003) call “libertarian paternalism.”17 Libertarian
paternalism is a philosophy that advocates designing institutions that
help people make better decisions but do not impinge on their freedom
to choose. Automatic enrollment is a good example of libertarian pa-
ternalism. Notice that firms must decide what happens to employees
who take no action with respect to joining the savings plan. Traditionally,
employees who did nothing were presumed not to want to join the plan.
17
For a brief summary of this idea, see Thaler and Sunstein (2003).
S186 journal of political economy
Automatic enrollment simply changes that presumption. Neither ar-
rangement infringes on choice (so both are libertarian), but one pro-
duces higher savings rates and so might be considered paternalistic. The
SMarT plan is even less intrusive than automatic enrollment since par-
ticipants have to take some action to enroll, and it is even more suc-
cessful at getting people to save. So, we plead guilty to the charge of
trying to be paternalistic, but since we are striving for libertarian pa-
ternalism, we do not think that it should be considered objectionable.
Finally, we hope that this study serves as a valid reply to two frequent
critiques of behavioral economics: the reliance on laboratory studies
using modest stakes and the ex post explanation of anomalous facts,
drawing on what is alleged to be a limitless store of potential behavioral
explanations. Here, we have used behavioral principles to design a plan
to increase savings rates and tested the idea in the real world.
References