Simondon Contra New Materialism
Simondon Contra New Materialism
Andrea Bardin
Oxford Brookes University
Abstract
This paper responds to an invitation to historians of political thought to enter the
debate on new materialism. It combines Simondon’s philosophy of individuation with
some aspects of post-humanist and new materialist thought, without abandoning a
more classically ‘historical’ characterization of materialism. Two keywords drawn
from Barad and Simondon respectively – ‘ontoepistemology’ and ‘axiontology’ –
represent the red thread of a narrative that connects the early modern invention
of civil science (emblematically represented here by the ‘conceptual couple’
Descartes-Hobbes) to Wiener’s cybernetic theory of society. The political stakes
common to these forms of mechanical materialism were attacked ontologically, epis-
temologically and politically by Simondon. His approach, I will argue, opens the path
for a genuine materialist critique of the political anthropology implicit in modern
political thought, and shifts political thinking from politics conceived as a problem to
be solved to politics as an arena of strategic experimentation.
Keywords
Barad, Descartes, Hobbes, new materialism, political anthropology, Simondon, Wiener
immutable ‘laws’ in both the natural and social sciences, along with the
foundationalist project attached to it since early modernity. What the sys-
tematic form of Simondon’s main works may conceal is the radical com-
mitment to conceptual experimentation that animates the encyclopaedic
enterprise he intended to carry on beyond phenomenology and structural-
ism. Simondon’s theory of individuation distanced itself at the same time
from the anthropocentrism implicit in the phenomenological concept of
sense, and the structuralist mechanization of social dynamics, vindicating
the experimental and inventive role played by philosophical thinking within
society. Entitled neither to assume a supreme function of epistemological
foundation nor to establish a privileged point of view over nature, for
Simondon philosophy is always playing catch-up with the historical
changes of technoscience as well as the complexity of material processes.
Far from this being a mark of frailty, it commits philosophy to play a
somewhat ‘interstitial’ yet crucial role in all the fields of scientific research,
which can still be a guide for the practice of materialist thinking today.
The present article specifically stresses the connection between ontol-
ogy, epistemology and political thought in Simondon’s theory of indi-
viduation and uses it as a materialist tool to challenge the modern
conception of a political theory based on the knowledge of (the laws
of) human nature, and the relation it implied between political thought
and the practice of politics. Two philosophical questions thus form the
leitmotif of the paper: How do we theorize the natural and the social, and
the knowledge of the human they produce together? How should we
relate science and politics, knowledge and political decision and action?
Implicit in these two questions is the problem of how to relate science
and politics without reducing one to the other, either by collapsing pol-
itics into techno-scientific planning (that is, technocracy) or by reducing
technoscience to an instrument of the pure voluntarism of political deci-
sion (that is, fascism). After a brief premise and partial vindication of
what I name – borrowing Engels’ expression – ‘vulgar’ mechanical
materialism, I will introduce the two keywords that – drawn from
Barad and Simondon – will orient my reflection: ‘ontoepistemology’
and ‘axiontology’. I will then develop my narrative, which connects the
early modern invention of ‘civil science’ within the conjuncture
Descartes-Hobbes up to Norbert Wiener’s cybernetics, by exploring
some passages where Simondon sketches a critique of modern mechan-
ical philosophy, and others where he assesses the political implications of
Wiener’s cybernetic theory of society.
My final suggestion is that the study of Simondon’s philosophy of
individuation, and notably his concept of ‘metastability’, can help us
take a step beyond the modern understanding of politics as a problem
posed by the ‘social unsociability’ of human nature and to be solved by
either a universal theory of politics or a blind commitment to political
decisionism. It is my wager that Simondon’s philosophy of individuation
28 Theory, Culture & Society 38(5)
helps explore what materialism can still offer to political thought, beyond
those versions of materialism that were and are integral parts of this
modern view of politics, and therefore unable to challenge it. A genuine
materialist approach, I will argue, allows us to shift political thinking
from the search for a universal solution based on what human nature is
assumed to be to politics as a strategic experimentation on what human
nature can become.
And this is Simondon’s reply to Ricœur during the debate following the
presentation of his paper Forme information potentiels at the Socie´te´
Française de Philosophie:
But how can one admit that nature is part of the discourse? This is
the postulate grounding your argument, and I will reject it abso-
lutely [. . .] No, there is a theory of speech far in excess of what might
be admitted; it is giving value to speech. There is a theory of nature,
in what I have tried to present. (Simondon, 2019: 579, 582)
Such a method, or rather operation, or, even better, such a ‘gesture’, will
require individual formulations and individual answers, or – to put it in
‘post-Simondonian’ terms – it will require axiontological decisions, and a
Bardin 39
Acknowledgements
Earlier versions of this work were presented in 2018 and 2019 at the Université de
Montréal, Universidade de São Paulo, King’s College London, Leuphana Universität
Lüneburg, Università degli Studi di Padova, and the Culture, Identities and Divisions
research group at Oxford Brookes University. I would like to thank all the convenors
and the audience members, as well as the three anonymous reviewers, for their questions
Bardin 41
ORCID iD
Andrea Bardin https://orcid.org/0000-0001-7228-8195
Notes
1. The concept of ‘allagmatics’ is central to Simondon’s two programmatic texts
Allagmatique and Analyse des crite`res de l’individualite´, first published in the
1995 (posthumous) edition of L’individu et sa gene`se physico-biologique, mod-
erately diffused in L’individuation (Simondon, 2005) and then disappears
from his writings. We cannot say for sure whether Simondon’s idea of allag-
matics corresponds to the theory of individuation he elaborates during the
1950s, but this is my hypothesis (cf. Bardin, 2015: 13–18). What we know for
sure is that the ‘allagmatics’ he has in mind should be ‘scientific and philo-
sophical’ study of the structures and processes generating the ‘individuated
being’ (Simondon, 2016a: 198–99, 2005: 565).
2. Again, Simondon got it right when he saw Descartes’s ontology as entailing a
technocratic normativity: ‘The cartesian continuum [. . .] is not only a meta-
physical statement: it is also the axiom – at the same time ontological and
axiological – founding a way of thinking whose basic schemas coincide with
those of a purely technical operation of construction’ (Simondon, 2014b:
104).
3. The expression first appeared in the article ‘Une nouvelle science: la cyberne-
tique – Vers la machine à gouverner’, published in the newspaper Le Monde
on 28 December 1948. The author was – quite critically – introducing to the
French audience the publication of Wiener’s Cybernetics or Control and
Communication in the Animal and the Machine in Paris, with the publisher
Hermann.
4. Simondon uses the terms ‘individuation’ and ‘ontogenesis’ interchangeably
(cf. Merleau-Ponty, 1959: 41).
5. However close Simondon’s philosophy may be to Deleuze’s reading of
Spinoza (Scott, 2017), there is no way to directly interpret Simondon as a
Spinozist. Étienne Balibar has recently pointed out that Simondon ‘generally
refuses to situate himself on the [Spinozian] terrain of philosophical anthro-
pology’ (Balibar, 2018: 6). Indeed, it was early noted by Filippo Del Lucchese
(2009) that Simondon’s sparse remarks show a quite unelaborated interpret-
ation of Spinoza’s philosophy. In Individuation Spinoza is pictured as a ‘hol-
istic’ thinker to be criticized for his reduction of individuality to substance as
a whole. As most of these readers have rightly intuited, Spinoza can, however,
be used as a key to the understanding of Simondon’s search for a relational
and processual ontology.
6. One might say that, while in Individuation à la lumie`re des notions de forme et
d’information Simondon explicitly aims at ‘reforming’ the cybernetic concept
of information, in Du mode d’existence des objets techniques – though in a
more ‘implicit’ fashion – he is challenging the (pseudo)cybernetic idea of
machines à gouverner.
42 Theory, Culture & Society 38(5)
7. In this sense the ‘idea of the individual as a ‘‘theatre’’ rather than an ‘‘agent’’
of individuation’ (Toscano, 2006: 150) fits more Deleuze than Simondon. For
Simondon the individual is both ‘agent’ (as a structure) and ‘theatre’ (as a
system) of individuation. In this sense he claims, for instance, that ‘the living
is both the agent and the theatre of individuation’ (Simondon, 2005: 29). For
the inception of Deleuze’s employment of Simondon’s concepts, see Deleuze’s
(1966) review of Simondon’s The Individual and Its Physico-Biological
Genesis. Cf. also Andrew Iliadis (2013: 95ff).
8. See also Karen Barad’s notion of apparatuses as ‘boundary-making practices’
(Barad, 2007: 148, 169 ff.).
References
Ashby, William Ross (1962) Principles of the self-organisation system. In Von
Foester, H. and Zoff, G.W. (eds) Principles of Self-Organization: Transactions
of the University of Illinois Symposium on Self-Organization, 8–9 June 1961.
Oxford: Pergamon Press, pp. 255–78.
Balibar, Étienne (1997) Spinoza: From individuality to transindividuality.
Mededelingen vanwege Het Spinozahuis 71: 3–46.
Balibar, Étienne (2018) Philosophies of the transindividual: Spinoza, Marx,
Freud, trans. M.E.G. Kelly. Australasian Philosophical Review 2(1): 5–25.
Barad, Karen (2003) Posthumanist performativity: Toward an understanding of
how matter comes to matter. Signs: Journal of Women in Culture and Society
28(3): 801–31.
Barad, Karen (2007) Meeting the Universe Halfway: Quantum Physics and the
Entanglement of Matter and Meaning. Durham: Duke University Press.
Bardin, Andrea (2015) Epistemology and Political Philosophy in Gilbert
Simondon: Individuation, Technics, Social Systems. Dordrecht: Springer.
Bardin, Andrea (2016) The monstrosity of matter in motion: Galileo, Descartes,
and Hobbes’s political epistemology. Philosophy Today 60(1): 25–43.
Bardin, Andrea and Rodriguez, Pablo (2018) A vindication of Simondon’s pol-
itical anthropology. Australasian Philosophical Review 2(1): 54–61.
Blanco, Javier and Rodriguez, Pablo (2015) Sobre la fuerza y la actualidad de la
teorı́a simondoniana de la información. In: Blanco, Javier, et al. (eds) Amar a
las máquinas: Cultura y te´cnica en G. Simondon. Buenos Aires: Prometeo
Libros, pp. 95–120.
Bontems, Vincent and De Ronde, Christian (2019) Simondon and quantum
mechanics (or, on how the ‘preindividual’ hypothesis leads to a realistic but
non-substantialist interpretation of the orthodox quantum formalism).
Philosophy Today 63(3): 611–624.
Choat, Simon (2018) Science, agency and ontology: A historical-materialist
response to new materialism. Political Studies 66(4): 1027–42.
Combes, Muriel (1999) Simondon. Individu et collectivite´, pour une philosophie du
transindividuel. Paris: PUF.
De Boever, Arne, et al. (eds) (2012) Gilbert Simondon: Being and Technology.
Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Deleuze, Gilles (1966) G. Simondon, L’individu et sa gene`se physico-biologique.
In: Deleuze, Gilles, L’ile de´serte et autres textes. Paris: Minuit, pp. 120–124.
Bardin 43