Force To Change Large Cardinal Strength
Force To Change Large Cardinal Strength
5-2015
This work is made publicly available by the City University of New York (CUNY).
Contact: [email protected]
Force to change large cardinal strength
by
Erin Carmody
2015
i
ii
©2015
Erin Carmody
Linda Keen
Arthur W. Apter
Gunter Fuchs
Philipp Rothmaler
Roman Kossak
Supervisory Committee
Abstract
by
Erin Carmody
This dissertation includes many theorems which show how to change large cardinal prop-
erties with forcing. I consider in detail the degrees of inaccessible cardinals (an analogue of
the classical degrees of Mahlo cardinals) and provide new large cardinal definitions for de-
grees of inaccessible cardinals extending the hyper-inaccessible hierarchy. I showed that for
every cardinal , and ordinal ↵, there is a notion of forcing P such that is still -inaccessible
in the extension, for every < ↵, but not ↵-inaccessible. I also consider Mahlo cardinals
and degrees of Mahlo cardinals. I showed that for every cardinal , and ordinal ↵, there is
a notion of forcing P such that for every < ↵, the cardinal is still -Mahlo in the exten-
sion, but not ↵-Mahlo. I also show that a cardinal which is Mahlo in the ground model
can have every possible inaccessible degree in the forcing extension, but no longer be Mahlo
there. The thesis includes a collection of results which give forcing notions which change
large cardinal strength from weakly compact to weakly measurable, including some earlier
work by others that fit this theme. I consider in detail measurable cardinals and Mitchell
v
rank. I show how to change a class of measurable cardinals by forcing to an extension where
all measurable cardinals above some fixed ordinal ↵ have Mitchell rank below ↵. Finally,
I consider supercompact cardinals, and a few theorems about strongly compact cardinals.
Here, I show how to change the Mitchell rank for supercompactness for a class of cardinals.
vi
Aknowledgements
First of all, I would like to thank Arthur Apter for helping me see the future. His en-
couragement has inspired me to see how bright our future is together. I have total faith and
trust in Arthur. We work well together. It makes me feel good when we can talk about
interesting problems together, and I look forward to all of our theorems of the future!
From the beginning until the end of this process, Philipp Rothmaler has been a great
mentor to me. He encouraged me to present at seminar, and helped me fall in love with
logic. Thank you Philipp for letting me tell you my ideas and for always being nearby to see
me through until the end. I was your student, and I look forward to our work together in
the future.
Gunter, thank you for being my friend and my mentor through this process. You have
always been there for me, and showed your appreciation of my interests. Your mind is amaz-
ing, and I always learn so much from your talks. I would like to know more, and create
Victoria, dear Victoria! You inspire me and you helped me so much. You took the time
to look at every word of my thesis and applications. You became my sister over time from
vii
the oral exam until now where we have our work together. I pray that I can find your kind
Dear Roman, thank you for encouraging me in every way possible. Thank you for being
a reliable source of support, and for showing your appreciation. Thank you for everything,
Roman.
Joel is never-waivering and ever-patient. To see him teach is to watch lightning in a bottle,
like an angel defending the line between heaven and hell. He is enthusiastic and gives 100%
all the time. His brain moves fast like a computer and his mind is as gentle as a breeze. He
is kind and aware. He helped me learn how to be a person through his actions and words.
I would also like to thank my pre-committee: Kaethe Minden, Miha Habic, and Kameryn
Williams. Thank you for forcing me to come to your wonderful seminar to get ready for the
final examination. I could not have done it without your thoughtful comments and friendship
all through my time as a student. You all are brilliant and I know that you are going to
create beautiful theorems and change the future of set theory and mathematics.
viii
Contents
1
1. Introduction
Large cardinals are infinite numbers, so big that we cannot prove their existence in ZFC.
If is a large cardinal, then V |=ZFC, so proving the existence of a large cardinal would
violate Godel’s incompleteness theorem. The theorems in the following chapters assume the
consistency of ZFC with large cardinals. Forcing was developed by Cohen in 1963, and has
been used as a way to prove independence results. Forcing in the following chapters is used
to create an extension where one or many large cardinals has some greatest desired degree
of some large cardinal property. Suppose 2 V is a cardinal with large cardinal property A.
The purpose of this thesis is to find a notion of forcing P such that if G ✓ P is V -generic, the
cardinal no longer has property A in V [G], but has as many large cardinal properties below
A as possible. The main theorems of this dissertation are positive results like this where
the large cardinal properties of a cardinal change between the ground model and the forcing
extension. A notion of forcing P which can change a large cardinal, like the ones in the main
theorems, does so carefully. That is, P does not just destroy large cardinal properties, it also
preserves large cardinal properties. The project is to pick a desired large cardinal degree
and design a notion of forcing which forces a cardinal to lose all large cardinal properties
above this degree and keep all large cardinal properties below. In other words, we are killing
large cardinals as softly as possible. In particular we are killing large cardinals by just one
degree from the ground model to the forcing extension. Thus, a part of this thesis is also
2
devoted to defining degrees of various large cardinal properties such as inaccessible, Mahlo,
able cardinal having two properties exhibited by !, the first infinite cardinal. Namely, an
inaccessible cardinal is regular: cof() = , just like ! since no sequence of finite length
can be cofinal in !, and an inaccessible cardinal is also a strong limit: 8 < , 2 <
just like ! since 8n < !, 2n < !. But inaccessible cardinals are uncountable, unlike !. An
cardinal. A cardinal is ↵-inaccessible if and only if is inaccessible and for every < ↵,
is a limit of -inaccessible cardinals. The main theorem of the first chapter is that if
chapter, I define ↵-hyper -inaccessible cardinals and beyond this to the richly-inaccessible
The second chapter is about forcing to change degrees of Mahlo cardinals. A Mahlo
cardinal has many inaccessible cardinals below, every closed unbounded (club) subset of
contains an inaccessible cardinal. Let I(X) be an operator which gives the set of inaccessible
limit points of a set X. A cardinal is called greatly inaccessible if and only if there is a
3
uniform, normal filter on , closed under I(X). The first theorem of the second chapter
shows that a greatly inaccessible cardinal is equivalent to a Mahlo cardinal. Since greatly
inaccessible cardinals are every possible inaccessible degree, as defined in chapter 1, Mahlo
cardinals are every possible inaccessible degree defined. One of the main theorems of the
second chapter is to force a Mahlo cardinal to lose its Mahlo property in the extension
while preserving that is every inaccessible degree defined. There is also a classical hierarchy
of Mahlo cardinal degrees, like the hierarchy of inaccessible cardinal degrees defined in the
first chapter. A cardinal is 1-Mahlo if and only if the set of Mahlo cardinals below is
only if is Mahlo and for all < ↵ the set of -Mahlo cardinals is stationary in . The
main theorem of the second chapter is that for any and ↵ where is ↵-Mahlo in V there
The third chapter involves many large cardinal notions. A few of the theorems in chapter
three are about weakly compact cardinals. A cardinal is weakly compact if and only if
is inaccessible and for every tree of height whose levels have cardinality less than has a
branch of length . One theorem shows that weakly compact cardinals are every classical
Mahlo degree. Another shows that one can force a weakly compact cardinal to lose its weak
compactness in the extension while keeping all of its Mahlo degrees. This chapter includes
theorems by others, especially Victoria Gitman about weakly compact cardinals and the
following large cardinal properties which are defined in chapter three: weakly measurable
The fourth chapter is about measurable cardinals, which have all of the large cardinal
properties described so far. A cardinal is measurable if and only if it is the critical point
cardinals is the Mitchell rank, denoted o() for a cardinal , is defined in chapter four. In
this chapter we are able to force to change the Mitchell rank for a class of cardinals in the
ground model. The main theorem is that for any V |= ZFC, any ↵ 2 Ord, and any > ↵
in V , there is a forcing extension V [G] where o() = min{↵, o()V }. In other words, in the
forcing extension every large cardinal above ↵ has Mitchell rank at most ↵.
The fifth and final chapter of this dissertation is about supercompact and strongly compact
j : V ! M with critical point and M ✓ ✓ M . That is, the target of the elementary
there is a -complete fine measure on P ✓. The first main results of the fifth chapter are
due to a key result by Hamkins and Shelah and show how to force a supercompact (or
strongly compact) cardinal to be at most ✓-supercompact (or ✓-strongly compact) for a fixed
✓. Also, Magidor’s result that one can force to separate strongly compact and supercompact
cardinals is in this chapter. In chapter five, Mitchell rank for ✓-supercompact cardinals,
denoted o✓-sc (), for a cardinal is discussed in detail. The main result shows how to find a
forcing extension where for many , ↵, ✓ in V the Mitchell rank for ✓-supercompactness for
In this section, I have found forcing extensions where the degree of an inaccessible cardinal
is reduced to an exact specified amount from its degree in the ground model. In general
terms, for a given cardinal , we find a notion of forcing which simultaneously preserves
large cardinal properties of up to some level while destroying its large cardinal properties
above that level. Suppose is a cardinal with large cardinal property A. Thus, also has
property B for any lower property B which follows from A. The objective is to find a forcing
notion P, with generic object G ✓ P, such that in the forcing extension, V [G], the cardinal
no longer has property A, but still has property B. The main theorem below shows how
to do this when the di↵erence between A and B is one degree of inaccessibility. An infinite
A cardinal is ↵-inaccessible if and only if is inaccessible, and for every < ↵, the cardinal
The following Lemma establishes some basic facts about degrees of inaccessible cardinals.
6
true that for every < 0, the cardinal is a limit of -inaccessible cardinals.
the cardinal is a limit of ⌘-inaccessible cardinals. Since every less than is also less
than ↵, the cardinal is a limit of -inaccessible cardinals, for every < . Thus, is also
-inaccessible.
3. By way of contradiction, suppose is the least cardinal with the property that
cardinals. Thus, there is a cardinal < for which is -inaccessible. Since is a limit
that is the least cardinal with this property. It follows from the lemma that cannot
( + 1)-inaccessible. ⇤
Proof. Let be ↵-inaccessible. If is not (↵ + 1)-inaccessible, then trivial forcing will give
the forcing extension where is ↵-inaccessible, but not (↵ + 1)-inaccessible. Thus, assume
(↵ + 1)-inaccessible but still ↵-inaccessible. The idea of the proof is to add a club, C, to
which contains no ↵-inaccessible cardinals, and then force to change the continuum function
to kill strong limits which are not limit points of C. To change the continuum function, we
Easton forcing to change the continuum function works when the GCH holds in the ground
model. For our purposes, we only need the GCH pattern to hold up through , by forcing
with P, which is a -length iteration of Add( , 1) for regular 2 V P . The forcing P, neither
destroys, nor creates, inaccessible cardinals below , and thus is a mild preparatory forcing,
so that we are in a place from which we will eventually perform Easton forcing.
First, see that P does not destroy inaccessible cardinals, by investigating its factors. Let
⌘ < be inaccessible, and let p 2 P. Let p be the condition, p, restricted to domain [0, ].
And, let p> , be the condition, p, with domain restricted to ( , ]. Let P = {p : p 2 P}
and P> = {p< : p 2 P}, so that P factors as P ⇤ P> . For < ⌘, the first factor,
P , is small relative to ⌘, and thus cannot force 2 ⌘. And, the second factor, P> , is
-closed, so adds no new subsets to . Thus ⌘ is still a strong limit after forcing with P.
Similar factoring arguments show that ⌘ remains a regular limit after forcing with P [Jech,
232+]. Since P preserves inaccessible cardinals, it follows by induction, that it preserves any
8
it follows by induction, that P cannot create -inaccessible cardinals for any < . Let
G ✓ P be V -generic, and force to V [G], where V [G] |= GCH, and where V and V [G] have
Next, force with C, which will add a club subset to , which contains no ↵-inaccessible
V [G]-generic, and let C = [H. Then, it is claimed that C is club in , and contains no
↵-inaccessible cardinals in V [G][H]. First, let us see that C is unbounded. Let 2 , and
d = c [ { 0 }, where 0
> and 0
is not ↵-inaccessible, is a condition in D and d is stronger
0 0 0
unbounded, there is 2 C, where > , and a condition c 2 C which contains . Since
the conditions are ordered by end-extension, and since there is a sequence (possibly of length
preserves cardinals, cofinalities and strong limits. The new club, C, does not contain any
ground model ↵-inaccessible cardinals, since if it did, there would be a condition in G which
To see that the new club, C, contains unboundedly many ground model -inaccessible car-
dinals, for every < ↵, fix < ↵ and ⌘ < . Let D⌘ be the set of conditions in C which
c 2 C. Let be the next -inaccessible above both ⌘ and and the maximal element of c.
Since is the next -inaccessible past ⌘ and < ↵, there are no ↵-inaccessible cardinals
in (⌘, ]. Also, this block, (⌘, ], contains the tails of all sequences of inaccessible cardinals,
contains a -inaccessible above ⌘, and a sequence of inaccessible cardinals which witness that
is -inaccessible. Thus, d 2 D⌘ , which shows that D⌘ is dense in C, and thus shows that
C contains unboundedly many -inaccessible cardinals. From this fact also follows, that,
in the final extension, is still ↵-inaccessible, as we shall soon see. Finally, the forcing C
preserves cardinals and cofinalities greater than or equal to + 1, forcing over V [G] |= GCH,
sequence of conditions unbounded in , but no condition could close the sequence since it
10
would have to include . However, for every < , the set D = {d 2 C : max(d) } is
dense in C and is -closed. This is true, since for any -sequence of conditions in D , one
can close the sequence by taking unions at limits and adding the top point, which cannot
be inaccessible, because it is not regular, since this top point is above , but has cofinality
. Thus, for every < , the forcing, C, is forcing equivalent to D , which is -closed.
Thus, C preserves all cardinals, cofinalities, and strong limits. Thus. V [G][H] |= GCH and
The last step of the proof is to force over V [G][H], with E, Easton’s forcing to change the
+
continuum function. Specifically, let E force 2 = +
, where 2 C, for infinite, and
+
is the next element of C past . This forcing preserves all cardinals and cofinalities [Jech,
232+], and also preserves that is inaccessible since factoring at any < reveals that the
first factor is too small to force 2 up to , and the second factor adds no new subsets to ,
thus preserving that is a strong limit cardinal, in addition to preserving that is a regular
limit cardinal. However, E does not preserve all inaccessible cardinals below . In fact, E
destroys all strong limits which are not limit points of C. Let ⌘ < be a strong limit which
is not in C 0 , the set of limit points of C. Since C is closed, there is a greatest element of
C below ⌘, call it . Then, the next element of C, call it , is greater than or equal to ⌘.
+
So, when E forces 2 = +
, it destroys that ⌘ is a strong limit since < ⌘ implies +
<⌘
Finally, see that since C 0 contains unboundedly many ground model -inaccessible cardi-
nals (which is the same as the set of -inaccessible cardinals in the intermediate extensions
since P and C preserve all inaccessible cardinals) for every < ↵. The cardinal is still
0
-inaccessible in V [G][H][K]. Let < , where 2 C 0 and is inaccessible. Since is a
0
limit point of C, the next element of C, call it , which is above , is also below , and
+ 0 0+ +
< since is a strong limit. Thus, 2 2 = < . So, is still a strong limit. Since
E preserves cardinals and cofinalities, this shows that is still inaccessible in the final ex-
tension. Thus, all inaccessible limit points of C are preserved. The earlier density argument
also shows that for any < ↵ it is dense that C contains an interval containing all cardinals
and also contains a -inaccessible cardinal. Since all limit points of such an interval are limit
points of C, it follows that all inaccessible cardinals in such an interval are preserved. Thus,
all degrees of inaccessible cardinals are preserved. If not, then suppose the least degree of
inaccessibility which is destroyed an ⌘-inaccessible cardinal for some ⌘ < ↵. Then for some
which implies that -inaccessible cardinals are destroyed, which contradicts that ⌘ was the
least degree not preserved. Thus, in V [G][H][K], for every < ↵, there are unboundedly
many -inaccessible cardinals below . Thus, is still ↵-inaccessible in the final extension.
⇤
12
extension, to be exactly ↵ when has degree at least ↵ in the ground model. The following
theorem shows how to force to a universe where there are no inaccessible cardinals, but
where every every ground model weakly inaccessible cardinal is still weakly inaccessible.
Theorem 3. For any V |= ZF C there exists V [G] with no inaccessible cardinals, but where
Proof. The proof is very similar to the proof of Theorem ??. It is a class forcing, where
the first step is to force that Ord is not Mahlo. We add a club C ✓ Ord such that C
contains no inaccessible cardinals. The second step is to perform Easton forcing to make
+ +
2 = whenever 2 C and where is the next element of C above . The idea of
the proof appears as a footnote in Hamkins[5]. The proof of Theorem ?? shows that the
combined forcing preserves all strong limits of C which are internally strong limits of C, and
destroys all strong limits of C which are not internally strong limits of C. Since C contains
no inaccessible cardinals, there are no inaccessible cardinals in the final extension. However,
as one can see from the proof of Theorem ?? or from Lemma ?? that the forcings preserve all
cardinals and cofinalities, so that all regular limit cardinals are preserved. Hence all weakly
↵ for some ↵ < . One can force to change a hyper-inaccessible cardinal to have maximal
degree by forcing to add a club which avoids all degrees above the desired degree, and then
force with Easton forcing to destroy strong limits which are not limit points of the new club,
Corollary 4. If is hyper-inaccessible, then for any ↵ < , there exists a forcing extension
Lemma ?? shows that the greatest degree of ↵-inaccessibility that can be is -inaccessible.
Mahlo began the investigation of degrees of inaccessible cardinals [Kan], and fully defined
the analgous notions for Mahlo cardinals, and I shall continue his work by formalizing the
degrees of inaccessible cardinals in the remainder of this section. So, how do we proceed
inaccessible denotes inaccessible). The following theorem shows we have again reached an
Proof. Suppose is the least cardinal with the property that is ( + 1)-hyper-inaccessible.
cardinal. Then, for every < , the cardinal is a limit of -hyper inaccessible cardinals.
This implies that for every < + 1 < , the cardinal is a limit of -hyper-inaccessible
In order to reach higher degrees of inaccessibility past this limit, repeat the process:
inaccessible cardinals. A cardinal is ↵-hyper2 -inaccessible if and only if, for every < ↵,
the cardinal is inaccessible and a limit of -hyper2 -inaccessible cardinals. By the same
argument from the previous proof, ↵ must be less than of equal to in this definition. And,
Thus, we arrive at the beginning of the formulation of the continuation of Mahlo’s work with
ample, 0-hyper0 -inaccessible is just inaccessible, since the second and third parts of the
ble and for all < ↵, the cardinal is a limit of -hyper0 -inaccessible cardinals, hence is
cardinals, for every < ↵, hence is ↵-hyper0 -inaccessible. And, 0-hyper-inaccessible is just
hyper-inaccessible since, from the general definition, this means that is inaccessible and
for every ⌘ < 1, the cardinal is -hyper⌘ -inaccessible, i.e., is -hyper0 -inaccessible, hence
hyper-inaccessible, but this requirement is included in the second part of Definition ?? since
theorem shows that a cardinal can be at most hyper -inaccessible, using this definition.
Proof. Suppose is the least cardinal with the property that is 1-hyper -inaccessible.
inaccessible. Then, for all < , the cardinal is -hyper -inaccessible. In particular, since
< , the cardinal is -hyper -inaccessible. This implies that is 1-hyper -inaccessible,
inaccessible, we need more words. Here, I will introduce new adjectives to describe higher
follow the same pattern as before to keep finding higher degrees past supposed obstacles:
is richly2 -inaccessible. Then, with these words, the greatest can be is richly -inaccessible.
Thus, define to be utterly-inaccessible if and only if is richly -inaccessible, so that the next
I will end this section with an exploration of how to characterize these degrees. Let I
be the class of inaccessible cardinals. Let I be the inaccessible limit point operator, a class
And, for classes X↵ , let ↵2ORD X↵ ={ : 2 \↵< X↵ } denote the diagonal intersection
of a collection (of classes). All of the degrees of inaccessible cardinals defined so far are also
I 0 (X) = X
\
I (X) = I (X)
<
Then, I 0 (I) = I, the class of inaccessible cardinals. And, I(I) = I 1 (I) is the class of
1-inaccessible cardinals, I 2 (I) is the class of 2-inaccessible cardinals, and so forth so that
I ↵ (I) is the class of ↵-inaccessible cardinals. Thus, the class of hyper-inaccessible cardinals
is
\
↵
↵2Ord (I (I)) = { : 2 I ↵ (I)}
↵<
↵
Let H = ↵2ORD (I (I)) be the class of hyper-inaccessible cardinals. Let H1 = I(H)
denoted H↵ . If we take the diagonal intersection of these classes we get H 2 = ↵2ORD (H↵ ),
the class of hyper2 -inaccessible cardinals. Then, applying the inaccessible limit point op-
erator to this class gives I(H 2 ) = H12 , the class of 1-hyper2 -inaccessible cardinals. Then
H3 = 2
↵2ORD (H↵ ), the class of hyper3 -inaccessible cardinals. Then, taking the diagonal
inaccessible cardinals. Applying diagonal intersection to this class gives HR = ↵2ORD (R↵ ),
the class of hyper-richly-inaccessible cardinals. Apply I to this class to get HR1 = I(HR),
hyper2 -richly-inaccessible cardinals. Proceed in this way to get H ↵ R, the class of hyper↵ -
↵
↵2ORD (H R), the class of richly2 inaccessible cardinals. Build up the classes, R↵ , of richly↵ -
↵
inaccessible cardinals and take the diagonal intersection of these to get U = ↵2ORD (R ),
The words hyper, richly, utterly, and so on mark places in the process of defining degrees
of classes. Thus, we have designed a notation system for the classes of inaccessible cardinals
using meta-ordinals. This notation system captures all the classes described so far, and can
go as far as you like. It is a notation system for meta-ordinals which is like Cantor’s normal
form for ordinals, but instead of ! we use ⌦, a symbol for the order-type of Ord. The degree
19
of any inaccessible cardinal will be denoted by t, a formal syntactic expression for a meta-
ordinal of the form ⌦↵ · +⌦⌘ · +· · ·+⌦· + where ↵ > ⌘ > · · · 2Ord, and , , , 2 Ord.
If s and t are meta-ordinals then the ordering is essentially lexicographical. If the degree on
⌦ of the leading term of t is greater than s, then s < t. If s and t have the same greatest
degree of ⌦, then compare the coefficients of the leading term. If these are the same, compare
the next highest powers of ⌦ in s and t and so on. Now that we have these meta-ordinals,
we can describe the classes of degrees of inaccessible cardinals in a uniform way. If ⌘ and
in the class of -inaccessible cardinals. But now I can describe both as being in the class
cardinals, for ↵ 2 Ord. Defined in this way, the degree of an inaccessible cardinal can be
described as t-inaccessible for some meta-ordinal t. The only restriction being that all of the
ordinals in t are less than or equal to . In this way, inaccessible cardinals with the same
t-inaccessible if and only if is inaccessible and for every meta-ordinal term s < t having
terms t with ordinals less than or equal to by replacing by ⌦. For example, a cardinal
⌦2 -inaccessible cardinal.
Here are a few of the classes described previously with this notation system:
is ⌦-inaccessible () is hyper-inaccessible
is ⌦2 -inaccessible () is richly-inaccessible
is ⌦3 -inaccessible () is utterly-inaccessible
is ⌦4 -inaccessible () is deeply-inaccessible
is ⌦5 -inaccessible () is truly-inaccessible
is ⌦6 -inaccessible () is eternally-inaccessible
is ⌦7 -inaccessible () is vastly-inaccessible
deeply-truly-eternally-vastly-inaccessible
Now that we have this uniform notation, we have the following theorem:
Proof. Sketch. The proof is very similar to the proof of Theorem ??. Assume V |= ZFC. Sup-
pose 2 V is t-inaccessible, where t is a meta-ordinal term with only ordinal exponents and
coefficients less than . Force with C. Conditions are closed, bounded subsets of such that
cofinalities. Since 8 < , the set D = {d 2 C : max(d) > } is dense, the new club C =
are closed. For every s < t, where s is a meta-ordinal term with ordinal parameters less than
+
Next force with E: For infinite 2 C, force 2 = +
where is the next element of C
past +
. E destroys strong limits which are not in C 0 : If ⌘ is a strong limit which is not a
+
limit point of C, then there is a maximal element of C below ⌘. Call it . Then < ⌘ and
+ +
the next element of C, call it , is above ⌘. Thus 2 = > ⌘ destroys that ⌘ is a strong
+
limit. If ⌘ 2 C 0 and ⌘ is a strong limit, then +
< ⌘ so 2 < ⌘ for every < ⌘. Thus, ⌘ is
Since C contains unboundedly many ground model s-inaccessible cardinals for s < t,
with a block of cardinals below them, then in the final extension these cardinals are still
22
However since all t-inaccessible cardinals below are no longer strong limits, is not t + 1-
inaccessible. ⇤
Finally, consider the connection between sets of inaccessible cardinals below and re-
this means that there is a tail [ , ) where, for each inaccessible in [ , ), there is, b , the
with f (↵) = ↵. Thus, for every ↵, there are no inaccessible cardinals between f (↵) and ↵.
is a tail of , with the property that there are no inaccessible cardinals between f (↵) and ↵
function f : ! such that for all inaccessible ↵ < , we have I 2 (I) \ (f (↵), ↵) = ;,
and there exists a regressive function g↵ : ! such that for all 2 (f (↵), ↵), we have
3. Mahlo Cardinals
This section begins with theorems about Mahlo cardinals, showing that Mahlo cardinals
have all the inaccessible large cardinal properties from the last section. An analogue of the
classical notion of greatly Mahlo is defined for inaccessible cardinals. Also, the classical
degrees of Mahlo cardinals are described, and theorems follow which show how to force a
large cardinal to have a desired Mahlo degree in the extension. An infinite cardinal is
Mahlo if and only if the set of inaccessible cardinals below is a stationary subset of . A
cardinal is greatly inaccessible if and only if there is a uniform, normal filter on , closed
A uniform filter on has for every < , the set [ , ) is in the filter, and normal means
that the filter is closed under diagonal intersections ↵< . The last part of the definition
means that if X is in the filter, so is I(X). The first theorem of this section shows that
Proof. For the forward implication, suppose is Mahlo. Let F be the filter generated by
sets of the form C \ I, where C is club in , and I is the set of inaccessible cardinals below
uniform, normal filter, closed under I. First, if C, D are club in , then C \ D is club. Thus,
for any clubs C and D, the equation (C \ I) \ (D \ I) = (C \ D) \ I implies that any set A
in the filter, generated by sets of the form C \ I, where C is club, is itself a superset of a set
the filter generated by sets of this form. Third, if A and B are elements of F , then there
This is of the form which generated the filter, thus A \ B 2 F . Also, F is uniform since
\ b 2 F . Since the cardinality of any co-bounded set is , the filter is uniform. It remains
to show that F is normal, and closed under the inaccessible limit point operation. To see
that F is normal, i.e. closed under diagonal intersection, see first that club sets are closed
under diagonal intersection. Let C↵ be club for every ↵ < . Then C↵ is closed, since,
if is a limit point of C↵ , then is a limit point of each C↵ , for ↵ < . To see this, let
↵ < . Then, since is a limit point of C↵ , there exists a such that ↵ < < , with
limit point of C↵ implies is a limit point of C↵ , for all ↵ < . Thus, since each C↵ is
25
To see that C↵ is unbounded, observe that for any < , the set \↵< C↵ is club. I’ll
show now that C↵ is unbounded, using this fact. Suppose that < . Since \↵< C↵ is
unbounded, there is 1 2 \↵< C↵ , with 1 > . Then since \↵< 1 C↵ is unbounded, there
where n+1 2 \↵< n C↵ . Taking the limit of this sequence, limn!1 n = !, and the limit
of the intersection of clubs gives that ! 2 \↵< ! C↵ , and ! > , since it is the limit of
Finally, for this direction, to show Mahlo implies greatly inaccessible, F is closed under I,
For the other direction, if is greatly inaccessible, then the uniform, normal filter, F , on
, contains all the club subsets of . This is true since all tails ( , ) are in F , since is
regular, and F is uniform, and all clubs can be written as the diagonal intersection of tails.
8
>
>
>
>
<[↵, ), if ↵ 2 C
AC
↵ =
>
>
>
>
:[ , ), if ↵ 2
/ C, where next element of C, past ↵
It is claimed that C = AC
↵ . Let x 2 C. Then, for every < x, the set AC contains [x, ),
C C
since the next element of C past is at most x. Thus, x 2 \ <x A so that x 2 <x A .
26
then either 2 C or the next element of C past is below x since x 2 AC . Thus, below x,
2 F , and I() = I 2 F , and for any club D ✓ , the set D is in F , and their intersection,
Theorem ?? below shows that a Mahlo cardinal is every degree of inaccessibility defined
previously. However, a cardinal being every degree of inaccessibility is not equivalent to the
cardinal being Mahlo. Theorem ?? separates the two notions with forcing to destroy the
Mahlo property of a cardinal, while preserving that the cardinal is every inaccessible degree.
Theorem 11. If is Mahlo, then for every meta-ordinal term t having ordinals less than
Proof. If is Mahlo, then is greatly inaccessible, by Theorem ??. Hence, there is a uniform,
normal filter F on , closed under the inaccessible limit point operation. Since 2 F , and
I() = I 2 F , all sets of ↵-inaccessible cardinals for ↵ < , below , are in F . And, since F
is normal, all sets of hyper inaccessible degrees below , which are all definable from diagonal
intersection, are in F . Hence, every set of inaccessible cardinals definable from I, I, and ,
27
in the manner of the previous section, by closing under these operations, is unbounded in
. ⇤
Theorem ?? of the last section shows that any cardinal which is at least ↵-inaccessible in
the ground model, for some ↵, can be made to be no more than ↵-inaccessible in a forcing
↵-inaccessible, but not Mahlo. The following theorem shows that if is Mahlo, there is a
forcing extension where is no longer Mahlo but still any degree of inaccessibility defined
Theorem 12. If is Mahlo, then there is a forcing extension where is t-inaccessible for
every meta-ordinal term t with ordinals less than or , but where is not Mahlo.
Proof. Let be a Mahlo cardinal. Let C be the forcing to add a club, C = [G, where
shows that C preserves cardinals, cofinalities, and all inaccessible cardinals in V . In fact,
V [G]
C did not change V at all, V = V . Since V has all the sets needed to define that is
all inaccessible degrees. Hence is still every possible inaccessible degree. However, is no
⇤
28
Just as there are infinitely many degrees of inaccessible cardinals, there are infinitely many
Mahlo degrees. One might be tempted to define the next degree of Mahlo to be a Mahlo
limit of Mahlo cardinals, exactly as was done with the degrees of inaccessible cardinals, and
indeed there is a hierarchy of Mahlo cardinals that can be defined this way. However, there
is a more powerful and appropriate way to define the degrees of Mahlo cardinals which is
much stronger. The definition of Mahlo cardinal is primarily about stationary sets, and
the degrees of Mahlo cardinals are classically defined by stationary sets. Thus, the classical
degrees of Mahlo cardinals are defined using stationary sets. Namely, an infinite cardinal
is 1-Mahlo if and only if is Mahlo, and the set of Mahlo cardinals below is stationary in
. In general, is ↵-Mahlo if and only if is Mahlo, and for every < ↵, the set of -Mahlo
The main theorem of this section will show how to force to change degrees of Mahlo
cardinals by adding a club avoiding a stationary set of cardinals of a certain Mahlo degree,
while preserving all stationary subsets of cardinals of a lesser Mahlo degree. A modification
of the forcing C, to add a club, from the proof of Theorem ??, will work. Given two sets
The following lemma shows that if A does not reflect in B, then the forcing to add a club
That is, if we force to add a club which avoids the strong set, then the stationarity of the
weak set and all of its stationary subsets will be preserved if the strong set does not reflect
in the weak set. In the proof of the theorem, the strong set will be Mahlo cardinals of a
fixed degree, and the weak set will be the set of Mahlo cardinals of a lesser degree which are
Lemma 13. If is Mahlo, and the sets A and B partition the inaccessible cardinals below
, where A does not reflect in B, then the forcing to add a club avoiding A will preserve all
the stationary subsets of B. Furthermore, the forcing does not add sets to V .
Proof. Suppose S 2 V is a stationary subset of B. Let P be the forcing to add a club through
the complement of A, and let Ė be a name for a club subset of , and p a condition which
substructure of hV , 2, A, B, Ėi. We can find such 2 S, since the set of giving rise to
of conditions below , deciding more and more about Ė, using the elements of c to guide the
given c↵ , choose c↵+1 to force a specific ordinal above ↵ into Ė with sup(c↵+1 ) 2 c, and at
and therefore is not in A, so that c is a condition for limit ordinals , in the construction.
That is, we can get through the limit steps below , precisely because c contains no points
30
stationary in the extension. Finally, this club shooting forcing does not add sets to V by
Lemma ??
The main result of this section is that if is ↵-Mahlo, then there is a forcing extension
where is still ↵-Mahlo, but no longer (↵ + 1)-Mahlo. That is, is forced to maximal Mahlo
degree, ↵-Mahlo. In fact, a very similar argument can be used to show that if is Mahlo
Theorem 14. If is ↵-Mahlo, then there is a forcing extension where is ↵-Mahlo, but
not (↵ + 1)-Mahlo.
Proof. Let ↵ < be fixed. Suppose is ↵-Mahlo. Let A be the set of ↵-Mahlo cardinals
below . Note that A does not reflect in its complement in the inaccessible cardinals, for if,
for some < , inaccessible, in the complement of A, the set of ↵-Mahlo cardinals below
to be an inaccessible cardinal in the complement of A. Thus, A does not reflect in the set of
If is not (↵ + 1)-Mahlo, then force trivially to show the result. Let C be the notion
of forcing which adds a club C through the complement of A. Conditions are ordered by
since A does not reflect in its complement, all stationary subsets of \A are preserved. Thus,
I only need to show that 8 < ↵ the set T = { < : is -Mahlo but not ( +1)-Mahlo }
As in the previous section for inaccessible cardinals (Definition ??), we can define the
3) for all < ↵, the set of -hyper -Mahlo cardinals below is stationary in .
32
Also, as in Definition ?? for degrees of inaccessible cardinals, we can define the classes of
Definition 16. If t is a meta-ordinal term having only ordinals less than , then a cardinal
is t-Mahlo if and only if for every meta-ordinal term s < t having only ordinals less than
Theorem 17. If is t-Mahlo, where t is a meta-ordinal term having parameters less than
, then there is a forcing extension V [G] where is t-Mahlo, but not (t + 1)-Mahlo.
Proof. Sketch. The proof is a generalization of the proof of Theorem ??. The proof is to
To end this section, we take a look at a large cardinal property below inaccessible, and
large cardinal properties just above inaccessible. A cardinal is worldly if and only if V
first theorem is about singular worldly cardinals, which are not inaccessible. A cardinal is
⌃n -worldly if and only if V satisfies the ⌃n fragment of ZFC. The following theorem shows
how to force a worldly cardinal to be ⌃n -worldly, but not ⌃n+1 -worldly [Hamkins3].
Theorem 18. (Hamkins) If ✓ is any singular worldly cardinal, then for any n 2 N, there is
The next theorem shows that it is not always possible to force between large cardinal
properties. It shows that if is inaccessible, there may not be a forcing extension where
Theorem 19. (Fuchs) If the existence of an inaccessible cardinals is consistent with ZFC,
then it is consistent with ZFC that a cardinal is inaccessible and has no forcing extension
Let me say a little about the proof. This proof will show that if is a regular worldly
cardinal, it may not be possible to force that is a singular worldly cardinal. Suppose is a
regular worldly cardinal and there is a forcing extension V [G] where is a singular worldly
cardinal. Then, by a covering lemma argument with the Dodd-Jensen core model, it follows
that is measurable in an inner model [Fuchs]. Since not all universes have inner models
with measurable cardinals, for some V and inaccessible, there is no extension where is a
The next theorem is about large cardinal properties just above inaccessible. A cardinal
⌃n -correct and inaccessible. The following theorems show how force to change degrees of
reflecting cardinals.
Proof. First, let us establish that all inaccessible cardinals are ⌃1 -reflecting. Then, we shall
prove the theorem by exhibiting a forcing notion which does not preserve that a cardinal is
⌃2 -reflecting, but which does preserve that the cardinal is inaccessible (hence ⌃1 -reflecting).
Suppose is inaccessible. It follows that V = H . The Lévy reflection theorem says that
is ⌃1 -reflecting. Let P be the canonical forcing of the GCH, and let G ✓ P be V -generic.
Next force over V [G] to make 2 = ++ in V [G][g], where g is V [G]-generic. Since the
canonical forcing of the GCH does not change that is inaccessible, and forcing 2 = ++
also cannot change that is a strong limit (or regular), it follows that is inaccessible in
V [G][g]. Thus is ⌃1 -reflecting in the final extension. However, V [G][g] = V [G] |= GCH
while V [G][g] |= 2 = ++ . Thus, is not ⌃2 -reflecting in V [G][g], since V [G][g] thinks the
In this section, forcing notions are found which distinguish pairs of large cardinals in the
[Mahlo, measurable] interval. The first theorem separates the notions of Mahlo and weakly
compact for a given cardinal with these properties. A cardinal is weakly compact if and only
if it is uncountable and satisfies the partition party ! ()2 . That is, is weakly compact if
and only if for every coloring of pairs of elements of into two colors, there is a homogeneous
inaccessible and have the tree property. An uncountable cardinal has the tree property
if every tree of height whose levels have cardinality less than has a branch of length
[Jech p. 120]. For example, !1 does not have the tree property since there exists an
tree of height with countable levels and no branches of length . And, CH implies there
is an !2 -Aranszajn tree, so in this universe, !2 does not have the tree property. A -Souslin
tree is a tree of height with no chains or antichains of size . Thus a -Souslin tree is a
-Aronszajn tree, since a chain is a branch. Thus, the existence of a -Souslin tree destroys
The following theorems are analogues of Theorem ?? and Theorem ?? from the previous
section. First, we see that every weakly compact cardinal is every degree of Mahlo.
36
Theorem 21. If is weakly compact then for every meta-ordinal term t having only ordinals
Proof. Suppose is weakly compact. By induction suppose is s-Mahlo for all s < t. We
want to show that is t-Mahlo. Fix any club C ✓ . Put C 2 M |= ZFC where M is
can assume V ✓ M . Since degrees of Mahloness are downward absolute the fact that is
Since the degrees of Mahlo cardinals discussed in the previous section are characterized
by stationary sets, it follows that if a notion of forcing preserves stationary sets, it preserves
any degree of Mahlo. This theorem shows how to force a weakly compact cardinal to lose
this property in a forcing extension while retaining that it is every possible degree of Mahlo.
Theorem 22. If is weakly compact, then there is a forcing extension where for every
meta-ordinal t having only ordinals less than , the cardinal is t-Mahlo but not weakly
compact.
Proof. Suppose is weakly compact. Let S be the forcing to add a -Souslin tree. Conditions
in S are normal trees of height ↵ + 1 for some ↵ < . The conditions in S are ordered by
required that for all T 2 S, the condition T is a normal tree: every element of T is a -length
binary sequence for some ↵, and if t ⇢ s and s 2 T then t 2 T , and every node splits in
two at every level, and for every node t and every level there is a node s at level which
extends t, and finally |T | < . Let G ⇢ S be V -generic. Let S = [G be the new tree. The
generic object S is a -Souslin tree [generalization of Jech p. 239]. These are the conditions.
The forcing notion S is -strategically closed since we can play the game along the paths
as not to get stuck at an Aronszajn tree of height less than . That is, the second player
keeps track of the paths which are played and always chooses nodes which continue paths
already chosen, so that at limits player two can continue play. Thus, S preserves stationary
sets. Thus, the forcing preserves that is any degree of Mahlo since the set of inaccessible
cardinals, set of Mahlo cardinals, set of 1-Mahlo cardinals, etc, below , remain stationary
in . However, since the new tree, S, is a -Aronszajn tree, it does not have a branch of
length . Therefore, no longer has the tree property, so it is no longer weakly compact.
if for every family A ✓ P (), of size at most + , there is a non-principal -complete filter
if and only if for every transitive set M of size + , with 2 M , there exists a transitive
N and an elementary embedding j : M ! N with critical point . For the next large
38
strongly Ramsey if every A ✓ is contained in a -model, M , for which there exists a weakly
regular cardinal is ine↵able if for every sequence hA↵ | ↵ < i, with A↵ ✓ ↵, there is A ✓
such that the set S = {↵ < | A \ = A↵ } is stationary. Measurable cardinals are weakly
measurable; weakly measurable cardinals are strongly Ramsey cardinals; strongly Ramsey
cardinals are not necessarily ine↵able cardinals, but are below strongly Ramsey cardinals in
consistency strength; and ine↵able cardinals are weakly compact. The following theorems
show how to force the di↵erence between these large cardinal properties for a given cardinal.
The following theorem, by Jason Schanker [Schanker], fits exactly in the theme:
The preservation part of the following theorem, and the forcing used, is due to Victoria
Gitman:
Theorem 24. If is strongly Ramsey, then there is a forcing extension where is not
way of contradiction, that is weakly measurable in the final extension. Let T 2 V [G][H]
be a slim--Kurepa tree, and let |M | = + , be a transitive set containing , the tree T , and
tree. But, since T has + many paths, and j(T ) is an end-extension of T , each of the +
many paths of T extends to a node on the th level of j(T ). Thus, there are + many nodes
on the th level of j(T ), and M can see all the paths of T . So, N can see that j(T ) is
The following theorem shows how to force to remove a large cardinal property while
consistent that the cardinal is also an ine↵able cardinal. However, the following theorem
shows how to force to an extension where is not ine↵able, but still strongly Ramsey.
Theorem 25. If is strongly Ramsey and ine↵able, then there is a forcing extension where
Proof. Suppose is ine↵able. The forcing to add a slim--Kurepa tree, as in the previous
theorem, will preserve that is strongly Ramsey [Gitman]. However, forcing to add such a
tree ensures that is not ine↵able in the extension since the characterization of ine↵able
5. Measurable cardinals
V.
The theorems in this section are about reducing Mitchell degrees of measurable cardinals in
a forcing extension. The Mitchell order is defined on normal measures; for normal measures
(and transitive) [Jech p. 358]. Thus, let m() be the collection of normal measures on .
The definition of rank for µ 2 m() with respect to C is o(µ) = sup{o(⌫) + 1 |⌫ C µ}.
The Mitchell order on , denoted o(), is the height of the Mitchell order on m(), thus
o() = sup{o(µ) + 1 | µ 2 m()}. If is not measurable, then o() = 0, since m() is empty.
measurable cardinals. A cardinal has Mitchell order o() 3, if and only if there is a
cardinal has o() ↵ if and only if for every < ↵, there is a normal measure on which
The following theorem shows how to force any measurable cardinal, of any Mitchell rank,
to have order exactly one. In the proof of the following theorem, and the proof of the
main theorems, we will need that the forcing notions do not create large cardinals. In the
previous sections, since being Mahlo or inaccessible is downwards absolute, we knew that
the forcing could not create new Mahlo or inaccessible cardinals. However, it is possible that
forcing create large cardinals in the extension. Therefore, we use the approximation and
cover properties of [Hamkins4] to ensure that no new measurable cardinals are created.
Theorem 26. If is a measurable cardinal, then there is a forcing extension where o() = 1.
In addition, the forcing will preserve all measurable cardinals and will not create any new
measurable cardinals.
rank o(µ) = 0, with cp(j) = , such that M |= is not measurable. Let P be a -length
43
iteration, with Easton support, of Q , a P -name for the forcing to add a club to of
cardinals which are not measurable in V , whenever < is inaccessible, otherwise force
trivially at stage . Let G ✓ P be V -generic, let Q̇G = Q, and let Q̇ be a P-name for a
forcing to add a club of cardinals to which are not measurable in V [G]. Let g ✓ Q be
V [G]-generic. Let 0 is the first inaccessible cardinal. This is the first non-trivial stage of
P, and at this stage a club is added to 0. Thus the forcing up to and including stage 0
has cardinality at most 0 and the forcing after stage 0 is closed up to the next inaccessible
cardinal. Thus, P has a closure point at 0. Thus by Corollary 22 in [Hamkins4], the forcing
that is measurable in V [G][g]. The main task is to find j(G), an M -generic filter for j(P),
and j(g) an M [j(G)]-generic filter for j(Q). Since the critical point of j is , the forcings P
and j(P) are isomorphic up to stage . Also, since Q̇ is a P-name for a forcing which adds
a club of ground model non-measurable cardinals to and V [G] and M [G] have the same
bounded subsets of , the forcing at stage of j(P) is Q̇. Thus, j(P) factors as P ⇤ Q̇ ⇤ Ptail ,
where Ptail is the forcing j(P) past stage . Since G is V -generic, it is also M -generic. Thus,
form the structure M [G]. Similarly, since g is V [G]-generic, it follows that g is M [G]-generic,
so construct the structure M [G][g]. Since both P and Q have size , they both have the + -
chain condition, so the iteration P ⇤ Q has the + -chain condition. Also, since j 00 = 2 M ,
The goal is to diagonalize to find an M [G][g]-generic filter for Ptail in V [G][g], and so far
we have satisfied one criterion which is that M [G][g] is closed under sequences in V [G][g].
Next, since |P| = , and 2 = + , it follows that P has at most + dense sets, and so does any
tail P[ ,) . Thus, Ptail has at most |j(+ )|V + = + dense subsets in M [G][g]. Finally,
since for every < , there is, in M [G][g], a dense subset of P which is -closed, there
M [G][g]-generic filter Gtail ✓ Ptail , in V [G][g]. Thus, j(G) = G ⇤ g ⇤ Gtail ✓ j(P) is M -generic,
and j 00 G ✓ G ⇤ g ⇤ Gtail . Therefore, the lifting criterion is satisfied, and so the embedding
The next goal is to lift the embedding through Q. The forcing j(Q) is the forcing to add
a club of non-measurable cardinals to j(), and we need an M [j(G)]-generic filter for j(Q).
Since Gtail 2 V [G][g], it follows that M [j(G)] ✓ M [j(G)]. Also, since |Q| = , it has at
most + many dense sets in V [G], by elementarity j(Q) has at most |j(+ )|V [G] + = +
many dense subsets in M [j(G)]. For any < , the forcing Q has a dense subset which
is -closed. Since < j(), the forcing j(Q) has a dense subset which is -closed.
Note that c = [g, which is club in , is in M [j(G)]. Let c̄ = c [ {}. For all < ,
since M ✓ M [j(G)] also satisfies approximation and cover properties, it follows that is not
subset of j() which contains no measurable cardinals. Thus c̄ 2 j(Q). Thus, diagonalize to
get a generic filter g ⇤ ✓ j(Q), in V [G], which meets a dense subset which is -closed, and
which contains c. Thus, let j(g) = g ⇤ , and observe that j 00 g ✓ g ⇤ since g 2 [g ⇤ . Thus, the
Finally o()V [G][g] 1 will follow from the fact that Q adds a club subset c ✓ which
contains no cardinals which are measurable in V . Since the combined forcing does not create
measurable cardinals, the club c contains no cardinals which are measurable in V [G][g]. Since
the new club has measure one in any normal measure on , the complement of c, which
contains the measurable cardinals of V [G][g] below has measure zero. Thus, there is no
Hence o()V [G][g] ⇧ 1. Thus, o() = 1 in V [G][g]. That the forcing preserves all measurable
cardinals and creates no new measurable cardinals will follow from the proof of the more
The previous theorem shows how to make the Mitchell order of any measurable cardinal
exactly one, for any measurable cardinal. The next theorem will show how to make the
Mitchell order of any measurable cardinal exactly ↵, for any ↵ < , in a forcing extension,
whenever the order is at least ↵. Preceding the proof are the following lemmas, so that we
which contains the singular cardinals. Then QS , the forcing to add a club C ⇢ S, preserves
cardinals and cofinalities, and for all < , the forcing QS has a -closed dense subset.
C = [G. Then C ✓ S is club in . First, see that C is unbounded. Let 2 , and let
condition: d = c [ { 0 }, where 0
> and 0
is in S. Then, d is an end-extension of c, hence
0 0
Suppose \ C is unbounded in < . Since C is unbounded, there is 2 C, where > ,
0
and a condition c 2 C which contains . Since the conditions are ordered by end-extension,
and since there is a sequence (possibly of length 1) of conditions which witness that \ C is
unbounded in C, which will all be contained in the condition c, which contains an element
< , then QS is not necessarily -closed. Let be the first limit of S which is not
for every < , the poset QS is forcing equivalent to C , which is -closed. Thus, QS
The following Lemma is about the Mitchell rank of a normal measure µ on a measurable
cardinal . By definition, o() is the height of the well-founded Mitchell relation C on m(),
the collection of normal measures on . Thus o() = {o(µ) + 1 | µ 2 m()}. Similarly the
is the ultrapower embedding by µ with critical point , then o(µ) = o()Mµ . Thus, < o()
if and only if there exists j : V ! M elementary embedding with critical point with
o()M = .
ultrapower embedding by µ with critical point . The model Mµ computes C correctly for
o()Mµ = sup{o(⌫)M⌫ + 1 | ⌫ 2 Mµ }
= sup{o(⌫)Mµ + 1 | ⌫ C µ}
= sup{o(⌫) + 1 | ⌫ C µ}
= o(µ)
Thus, the Mitchell rank of in Mµ is the Mitchell rank of µ. Let < o(). Since C is
the ultrapower by µ with critical point , then o()Mµ = o(µ) = , as desired. Conversely,
µ be the induced normal measure, using as a seed (X 2 µ if and only if 2 j(X)) and let
Mµ be the ultrapower by µ. Then M and Mµ have the same normal measures and the same
Mitchell order and ranks, so Mµ |= o() = . Since we have established o()Mµ = o(µ), the
Mitchell rank of µ in m() is , that is o(µ) = . Thus since o() = {o(µ) + 1|µ 2 m()},
satisfies the approximation and cover properties, then the Mitchell rank of a cardinal >
Lemma 29. Suppose V ✓ V̄ satisfies the approximation and cover properties. If > ,
Proof. Suppose V ✓ V̄ satisfies the approximation and cover properties. Suppose > .
We want to show o()V̄ o()V by induction on . Assume inductively that for all 0 < ,
we have o(0 )V̄ o(0 )V . If o()V̄ > o()V then by Lemma ?? get and elementary ultrapower
Again by ?? we have established that o()M < o()V . Thus, o()M < o()M̄ . However, this
contradicts that j applied to the induction hypothesis gives o()M̄ o()M since < j().
Lemma 30. If V ✓ V [G] is a forcing extension and every normal ultrapower embedding
o()V [G] o()V . In addition, if V ✓ V [G] also has approximation and cover properties,
Proof. Suppose V ✓ V [G] is a forcing extension where every normal ultrapower embedding
and for every measurable cardinal 0 < , assume o(0 )V [G] o(0 )V . Fix any < o().
Then, applying j to the induction hypothesis gives o()M [j(G)] o()M since < j().
Then, since M |= o() = it follows that o()M [j(G)] . Thus by Lemma ?? o()V [G] > .
If V ✓ V [G] also satisfies the approximation and cover properties, then by Lemma ??
the Mitchell rank does not go up between these models. Thus o()V [G] = o()V . ⇤
Theorem 31. For any V |= ZF C + GCH and any ordinal ↵, there is a forcing extension
V [G] where every cardinal above ↵ in V [G] has o()V [G] = min{↵, o()V }. In particular, if
1 ↵, then the forcing preserves all measurable cardinals of V and creates no new measurable
cardinals.
Proof. Let ↵ 2 Ord. The following notion of forcing will ensure that the Mitchell rank of all
cardinals above ↵ which have Mitchell rank above ↵ will change. Let P be an Easton support
implies o( )V < ↵. Let G ✓ P be V -generic. Let 0 denote the first inaccessible cardinal.
The forcing up to this stage, P 0 , adds nothing and the forcing Q at stage 0 adds a club
to 0, so that |P 0 ⇤ Q̇| 0. The forcing past stage 0 is closed up to the next inaccessible
+
V ✓ V [G] satisfies the 0 approximation and cover properties. Thus, by Lemma ?? the
Mitchell rank does not go up between V and V [G]. Note that any measurable cardinal is
+
above 0 .
51
Let be a measurable cardinal above ↵. Fix any 0 < min{↵, o()V }. The induction
hypothesis is that for all 0 < , we have o(0 )V [G] = min{↵, o(0 )V }. By Lemma ??, fix an
P. The forcing above does not a↵ect o() since the forcing past stage has a dense subset
which is closed up to the next inaccessible. Allow me to call P ⇤ Q̇ the forcing up to and
including stage while I am lifting the embedding, first through P and then through Q.
for j(P ). Since cp(j) = , the forcings P and j(P ) agree up to stage . Since ↵ < ,
where ↵ is the ordinal in the statement of the theorem, and the forcing Q adds a club c ✓
such that 2 c implies o( )V < ↵ which implies o( )M < ↵, it follows that the th stage
of j(P ) is Q. Thus, j(P ) factors as P ⇤ Q̇ ⇤ Ptail where Ptail is the forcing past stage .
Since G ⇤ g is generic for P ⇤ Q̇, we just need an M [G ][g]-generic filter for Ptail which
is in V [G ][g] (since we want the final embedding to be there). Thus, diagonalize to get
an M [G ][g]-generic filter for Ptail after checking we have met the criteria. Namely, since
|P | = |Q̇| = , the forcing P ⇤ Q̇ has the + -chain condition. Since M ✓ M , it follows
[Hamkins1 (Theorem 54)] that M [G ][g] ✓ M [G ][g]. Also, since 2 = + , the forcing P
has + many dense sets in V . Thus, Ptail has at most |j(+ )|V + = + many dense sets
in M [G ][g]. Also, since for any < , the forcing P has a dense subset which is -closed
(by Lemma ??), it follows that there is a dense subset of Ptail which is -closed. Thus, we
may diagonalize to get G⇤ ⇢ Ptail for this dense subset, a generic filter in V [G ][g], which is
52
Next, we lift j through Q. The forcing j(Q) adds a club C ✓ j() such that 2 C
(Theorem 53)] that M [j(G )] ✓ M [j(G )]. Also, by Lemma ??, there is a dense subset of
j(Q) which is -closed, and since |Q| = , it follows that j(Q) has at most + many dense
subsets in M [j(G )]. Let c = [g, which is club in , and consider the set c̄ = c [ {} 2
M [j(G )]. We have 2 c implies o( )V < ↵. Since M and V agree on P (P ( )) for < ,
implies o( )M [j(G )] < ↵. Since o()M < ↵, it follows that o()M [j(G )] < ↵, so that c̄ is
a condition of j(Q), since c̄ is a closed, bounded subset of j() which such that 2 c̄
implies o( )M [j(G )] < ↵. Thus, diagonalize to get an M [j(G)]-generic filter, g ⇤ ✓ j(Q) which
contains the condition c̄. Then j 00 g ✓ j(g) = g ⇤ . Therefore, we may lift the embedding to
From the previous lifting arguments will follow that o()V [G] min{o()V , ↵}. The lifted
embedding j : V ! M was chosen so that o()M = 0 < min{o()V , ↵}. Since 0 was
arbitrary, it follows from Lemma ?? that o()V min{o()V , ↵}. All that remains to see
is o()V [G] min{o()V , ↵}. By Lemma ??, which shows Mitchell rank does not go up for
V ✓ V [G], we have o()V [G] o()V . Consider any embedding j : V [G] ! M [j(G)] with
critical point in V [G], and the new club c ✓ , where 8 < , 2 c implies o( )V < ↵, which
53
Applying j to this statement gives, 8 < j(), 2 j(c) implies o( )M [j(G)] < ↵. Since
< j() and 2 j(c), this gives o()M [j(G)] < ↵. Thus by Lemma ??, since j was arbitrary,
o()V [G] ↵. Thus o()V [G] min{o()V , ↵}. Thus, o()V [G] = min{o()V , ↵}. ⇤
I would like to now consider cases where o() . For this we use the concept of
and M ✓ M , then j(f )() = ↵ (this can be formalized as a first-order statement using
extenders) [Hamkins2]. Let F : Ord ! Ord. The main theorem shows how to change the
Mitchell rank for all measurable cardinals for which F represents F ( ) (through any
Theorem 32. For any V |= ZF C + GCH and any F : Ord ! Ord, there is a forcing
extension V [G] where, if is measurable and F represents F () in V, then o()V [G] =
min{o()V , F ()}.
Proof. For example, we can do this for numerous functions satisfying this hypothesis, such
2
as F ( ) = , F ( ) = + 3, F ( ) = + ! 2 · 2 + 5, and any other function which can be
defined like this. Suppose V |= ZFC + GCH. Let F : Ord ! Ord. Let P be an Easton
that 2 C implies o( )V < F ( ). Let 0 denote the first inaccessible cardinal. The forcing
54
up to this stage, P 0 , adds nothing and the forcing Q at stage 0 adds a club to 0, so that
|P 0 ⇤ Q̇| 0. The forcing past stage 0 is closed up to the next inaccessible cardinal. Let
+
that V ✓ V [G] satisfies the 0 approximation and cover properties. Thus, by Lemma ?? the
need that representing functions are still representing functions in the extension. The fact
we will use for this is from [Hamkins4] which says that if V ✓ V [G] satisfies the hypothesis
of approximation and cover theorem, then every -closed embedding j : V [G] ! M [j(G)] is
Thus, if F is a representing function for F () in the ground model, (j V )(F )() =
F () = ↵, and thus F is a representing function for F () with respect to such embeddings
j in V [G].
The induction hypothesis is that for all 0 < for which F 0 represents F (0 ) in V has
o(0 )V [G] = min{F (0 ), o(0 )V }. By Lemma ?? fix an elementary embedding j : V ! M with
cp(j) = and o()M = 0 < min{o()V , F ()}. Note that j(F )() = j(F )() = F ().
We shall lift j through P. The forcing above does not a↵ect o() since the forcing past stage
is closed up to the next inaccessible. Allow me to call P ⇤ Q̇ the forcing up to and including
stage while I am lifting the embedding, first through P and then through Q. Let G ✓ P
be V -generic, and g ✓ Q be V [G ]-generic. First, we need an M -generic filter for j(P ).
55
Since cp(j) = , the forcings P and j(P ) agree up to stage . The forcing Q adds a club
C ✓ such that 2 C implies o( )V < F ( ). Since j(F )() = F () and o()M < F (),
the th stage of j(P ) is Q. Thus, j(P ) factors as P ⇤ Q̇ ⇤ Ptail where Ptail is the forcing
past stage . Since G ⇤ g is generic for P ⇤ Q̇, we just need an M [G ][g]-generic filter for
Ptail which is in V [G ][g] (since we want the final embedding to be there). Thus, we shall
diagonalize to get an M [G ][g]-generic filter for Ptail after checking we have met the criteria.
Namely, since |P | = |Q| = , the forcing P ⇤ Q̇ has the + -chain condition. Since M ✓ M ,
it follows [Hamkins1 (Theorem 54)] that M [G ][g] ✓ M [G ][g]. Also, since 2 = + , the
forcing P has + many dense sets in V . Thus, Ptail has at most |j(+ )|V + = +
many dense sets in M [G ][g]. Also, since for any < , the forcing P has a dense subset
which is -closed (by Lemma ??), it follows that there is a dense subset of Ptail which is
-closed. Thus, we may diagonalize to get G⇤ ✓ Ptail for this dense subset, a generic filter
in V [G ][g], which is M [G ][g]-generic. Thus, j(G ) = G ⇤ g ⇤ G⇤ is M -generic for j(P )
Next, we lift j through Q. The forcing j(Q) adds a club C ✓ j() such that 2 C
implies o( )M [j(G )] < j(F )( ). Since j(G ) 2 V [G ][g] and M ✓ M , it follows [Hamkins1
(Theorem 53)] that M [j(G )] ✓ M [j(G )]. Also, by Lemma ??, there is a dense subset of
j(Q) which is -closed, and since |Q| = , it follows that j(Q) has at most + many dense
subsets in M [j(G )]. Let c = [g and consider the set c̄ = c [ {}. By the construction of
By Lemma ?? it follows that 2 c implies o( )M [j(G)] < F ( ). Since o()M [j(G)] o()M =
56
0 < min{o()V , F () = ↵} it follows that o()M [j(G)] < ↵ = j(F )(). Thus c̄ is a closed,
bounded subset of j() such that if 2 c̄ then o( )M [j(G)] < j(F )( ). Thus c̄ is a condition
of j(Q). Thus, diagonalize to get an M [j(G)]-generic filter, g ⇤ ✓ j(Q) which contains the
condition c̄, so that j 00 g ✓ j(g) = g ⇤ . Therefore, we may lift the embedding to j : V [G ][g] !
M [j(G )][j(g)].
From the previous lifting arguments will follow that o()V [G] min{o()V , F ()}. The
lifted embedding j : V ! M was chosen so that o()M = 0 < min{o()V , F ()}. Since
0 was arbitrary, by Lemma ?? it follows that o()V [G] min{o()V , F ()}. All that is
left is to see that o()V [G] min{o()V , F ()}. By Lemma ?? which shows that Mitchell
rank does not go up for V ✓ V [G], we have o()V [G] o()V . Consider any embedding
j : V [G] ! M [j(G)] in V [G], and the new club c ✓ where 8 < , 2 c implies
statement to get 8 < j(), 2 j(c) implies o( )M [j(G)] < j(F )() = F (). Note that since
F () in M [j(G)] as well. Since j was arbitrary, < j(), and 2 j(c) it now follows
by Lemma ?? it follows that o()V [G] F (). Thus o()V [G] min{o()V , F ()}. Thus
⇤
57
This section begins with supercompact and strongly compact cardinals. The main theorem
and M ✓ ✓ M , where < ✓ < j(). Equivalently, is ✓-supercompact if and only if there is
a normal fine measure on P ✓. A fine measure in the previous sentence means a -complete
supercompact if and only if it is ✓-supercompact for every ✓ > . Notice that measurable
only if there is an elementary embedding j : V ! M , with critical point , such that for all
t ✓ M , where |t|V ✓, there is an s 2 M such that t ✓ s and |s|M < j(). Equivalently, a
cardinal is ✓-strongly compact for < ✓ if and only if there is a -complete fine measure on
and only if for any set S, every -complete filter on S can be extended to a -complete
ultrafilter on S [Jech p. 365]. The following theorems show how to distinguish, by forcing,
supercompact cardinals, between measurable and strongly compact cardinals, and between
there is a forcing extension where is < ✓-supercompact, but not ✓-supercompact, and indeed
Proof. Suppose is < ✓-supercompact for some regular ✓ > , and let P = Add(!, 1) ⇤
Add(✓, 1). By [Hamkins/Shelah], after forcing with P, the cardinal is not ✓-supercompact.
However, adding a Cohen real is small relative to , so the first factor of P preserves that
is < ✓-supercompact. The second factor of P is < ✓-closed, so that a normal fine measure
on P , where < ✓ is still a normal fine measure on P , since no new subsets of were
added. Let G ✓ P be V -generic. Thus, in V [G], the cardinal is < ✓-supercompact, but
not ✓-supercompact.
Corollary 34. If is ✓-supercompact where < ✓ and ✓< = ✓, then there is a forcing
<
Theorem 35. If is <✓-strongly compact, for ✓ regular with < ✓ for all < ✓,
then there is a forcing extension where is <✓-strongly compact, but not ✓-strongly compact.
Proof. Suppose is < ✓-strongly compact for regular ✓ , and let P = Add(!, 1)⇤Add(✓, 1).
a Cohen real is small relative to , so the first factor preserves that is < ✓-strongly compact.
Also, since the second factor is < ✓-closed, any -complete fine measure on P , where < ✓,
59
is still a -complete fine measure since there are no new subsets of to measure. Thus, P
preserves that is < ✓-strongly compact. Let G ✓ P be V -generic. Then, in V [G], the
Corollary 36. If is ✓-strongly compact, where ✓ and ✓< = ✓, then there is a forcing
The following theorem is due to Magidor [Magidor]. It shows how to force between strong
Theorem 38. (Magidor) If is strongly compact, then there is a forcing extension where
A word on the proof of the theorem. Suppose is a strongly compact cardinal. Then,
there is a forcing extension, V [G], where is the least strongly compact cardinal, and the
least measurable cardinal [Magidor]. However, the least measurable cardinal can never be
supercompact, since there are many measurable cardinals below any supercompact cardinal.
As for measurable cardinals, an analgous rank to Mitchell rank can be assigned to super-
normal fine measures on P ✓, define the Mitchell relation µC✓-sc ⌫ if and only if µ 2 M⌫ where
given and ✓, the Mitchell rank of µ is its rank with respect to C✓-sc . Thus, for fixed and
✓, the notation osc () = ↵ means the height of C✓-sc on normal fine measures on P ✓ is ↵. By
definition, o✓-sc () is the height of the well-founded Mitchell relation C✓-sc on m(), the col-
lection of normal fine measures on P ✓. Thus the definition of rank for µ 2 m() with respect
to C✓-sc is o✓-sc (µ) = sup{o✓-sc (⌫) + 1 |⌫ C✓-sc µ}. Thus o✓-sc () = {o✓-sc (µ) + 1 | µ 2 m()}.
So that o✓-sc () = 0 means that is not ✓-supercompact, and o✓-sc () > 0 means that is
✓-supercompact.
The main theorems of this section will rely on the following Lemmas about Mitchell rank
for supercompactness and are analogues of Lemmas ??, ??, and ?? for Mitchell rank.
computes C✓-sc correctly for ⌫ C✓-sc µ, which means ⌫ 2 Mµ , since M ✓ ✓ M , and so Mµ has
61
= o✓-sc (µ)
Thus, the Mitchell rank for supercompactness of in Mµ is the Mitchell rank of µ. Let
< o✓-sc (). Since C✓-sc is well-founded, there is µ a normal fine measure on P ✓ such
that o✓-sc (µ) = . Then if jµ : V ! Mµ is the ultrapower by µ with critical point , then
with cp(j) = and o✓-sc ()M = . Let µ be the induced normal fine measure, using j 00 ✓
M and Mµ have the same normal fine measures and the same Mitchell order and ranks for
✓-supercompactness, so Mµ |= o✓-sc () = . Since we have established o✓-sc ()Mµ = o✓-sc (µ),
the Mitchell rank for supercompactness of µ in m() is , that is o✓-sc (µ) = . Thus since
o✓-sc () = {o✓-sc (µ) + 1 | µ 2 m()}, it follows that o✓-sc ()V > .
The following Lemma is an analogue of Lemma ?? for degrees of Mitchell rank for super-
satisfies the approximation and cover properties, then no supercompact cardinals are created
from V to V̄ .
Lemma 40. Suppose V ✓ V̄ satisfies the approximation and cover properties. If , ✓ > ,
Proof. Suppose V ✓ V̄ satisfies the approximation and cover properties. Suppose , ✓ > .
We want to show o✓-sc ()V̄ o✓-sc ()V by induction on . Assume inductively that for all
0 < , we have o✓-sc (0 )V̄ o✓-sc (0 )V . If o✓-sc ()V̄ > o✓-sc ()V then by Lemma ?? get a ✓-
supercompactness embedding j : V̄ ! M̄ with critical point and o✓-sc ()M̄ = o✓-sc ()V . By
this embedding is a class in V . Again by ?? we have established that o✓-sc ()M < o✓-sc ()V .
Thus, o✓-sc ()M < o✓-sc ()M̄ . However, this contradicts that j applied to the induction
hypothesis gives o✓-sc ()M̄ o✓-sc ()M since < j(). Therefore, o✓-sc ()V̄ o✓-sc ()V . ⇤
then o✓-sc ()V [G] o✓-sc ()V . In addition, if V ✓ V [G] also has approximation and cover
Proof. Suppose V ✓ V [G] is a forcing extension where every normal ultrapower embedding in
and for every ✓-supercompact cardinal 0 < , assume o✓-sc (0 )V [G] o✓-sc (0 )V . Fix any <
63
o✓-sc (). By Lemma ?? there exists an elementary embedding j : V ! M with cp(j) = and
M |= o✓-sc () = . Then, by the assumption on V ✓ V [G], this j lifts to j : V [G] ! M [j(G)].
Then, applying j to the induction hypothesis gives o✓-sc ()M [j(G)] o✓-sc ()M since < j().
Then, since M |= o✓-sc () = it follows that o✓-sc ()M [j(G)] . Thus by Lemma ?? we have
o✓-sc ()V [G] > . Thus o✓-sc ()V [G] o✓-sc ()V .
If V ✓ V [G] also satisfies the approximation and cover properties, then by Lemma ??
the Mitchell rank does not go up between these models. Thus ✓-sc o()
V [G]
= o✓-sc ()V . ⇤
The following theorem shows how to force a + -supercompact cardinal to have Mitchell
Theorem 42. If V |= ZF C + GCH then there is a forcing extension where every cardinal
which is + -supercompact has o+ -sc ()V [G] = min{o+ -sc ()V , 1}.
Let G ✓ P be V -generic. Let 0 be the first inaccessible cardinal. The forcing before stage
0 is trivial, and the forcing at stage 0 adds a club to 0. Thus the forcing P up to and
including stage 0 has cardinality 0, and the forcing past stage 0 has a dense set which is
closed up to the next inaccessible cardinal. Thus P has a closure point at 0 which implies
+
V ✓ V [G] satisfies the 0 approximation and cover properties by [Hamkins4 (Lemma 13)].
Thus by [Hamkins4 (Corollary 26)], the forcing P does not create ✓-supercompact cardinals
64
for any ✓. Note that any ✓-supercompact cardinal , both ✓ and are above this closure
point.
Suppose is + -supercompact. The induction hypothesis is that any 0 < has o0+ -sc (0 )V [G] =
such that o+ -sc ()M = 0 < min{o+ -sc ()V , 1}. We shall lift j through P. The forcing above
does not a↵ect the Mitchell rank for + -supercompactness of since the forcing past stage
has a dense subset which is closed up to the next inaccessible cardinal past . Call P ⇤ Q̇
the forcing up to and including stage . First we shall lift j through P . Let G ✓ P be
V -generic and g ✓ Q be V [G ]-generic. First, we need an M -generic filter for j(P ). Since
cp(j) = , the forcings P and j(P ) agree up to stage . The forcing Q adds a club c ✓
follows that the th stage of j(P ) is Q. Thus, j(P ) factors as P ⇤ Q̇ ⇤ Ptail where Ptail is the
forcing past stage . Since G ⇤ g is M -generic for P ⇤ Q̇, we only need an M [G ][g]-generic
filter for Ptail which is V [G ][g]. We will diagonalize to obtain such a filter, after checking
that we have met the criteria. Since |P | = |Q| = , and V |= GCH, it follows that the
+
forcing P ⇤ Q̇ has the + -chain condition. Since M ✓ M , it follows [Hamkins1 (Theorem
+
54)] that M [G ][g] ✓ M [G ][g]. Since |P | = , and has the + -chain condition, it has at
<
+ +
most < = + many maximal antichains. Since |j(+ )| + = ++ , it follows that
Ptail has at most ++ many maximal antichains in M [G ][g]. Since Ptail has a dense subset
which is closed up to the next inaccessible past , it has a dense subset which is + -closed.
Thus, we can enumerate the maximal antichains of Ptail , and build a descending sequence of
65
conditions meeting them all through the dense set which has + -closure, using this closure
and the fact that M [G ][g] is closed under + -sequences to build through the limit stages.
Then the upward closure of this sequence Gtail ✓ Ptail is M [G ][g]-generic and is in V [G ][g].
Thus j(G ) = G ⇤ g ⇤ Gtail is M -generic, it is in V [G ][g] and j 00 G ✓ j(G ). Thus we have
Next we lift through Q by finding an M [j(G )]-generic filter for j(Q). The forcing j(Q)
adds a club C ✓ j() such that 8 < j(), 2 C implies o + -sc ( )M [j(G )] = 0. Since
+ +
j(G ) 2 V [G ][g] and M ✓ M , it follows that M [j(G )] ✓ M [j(G )] by [Hamkins1
(Theorem 53)]. Since for every < , there is a dense subset of Q which is -closed, it
follows that there is a dense subset of j(Q) which is + -closed. Also since |Q| = and Q has
the + -chain condition, the forcing Q has at most + many maximal antichains. Therefore
<
+
j(Q) has at most |j(+ )| + = ++ many maximal antichains in M [j(G )]. Thus we
can diagonalize to get a generic filter, but we will do so with a master condition as follows.
Let c = [g the new club of and consider c̄ = c [ {} which is in M [j(G )]. We have 2c
+
new -supercompact cardinals are created between M and M [j(G )], so that 2 c implies
o + -sc ( )M [j(G )] = 0. Since o+ -sc ()M = 0, it follows that o+ -sc ()M [j(G )] = 0. Thus c̄
is a closed, bounded subset of j() such that every in c̄ has o + -sc ( )M [j(G )] = 0. Thus
c̄ 2 j(Q). Thus diagonalize to get an M [j(G )]-generic filter g ⇤ ✓ j(Q) which contains
the master condition c̄. Then j 00 g ✓ j(g) = g ⇤ . Therefore we may lift the embedding to
The success of the lifting arguments show that o+ -sc ()V [G] min{o+ -sc ()V , 1}. By
Lemma ?? we have o+ -sc ()V [G] o+ -sc ()V . All that remains is to see that o+ -sc ()V [G]
in V [G], and the new club c ✓ , where 8 < , 2 c implies o + -sc ( )V = 0. This club
plies o + -sc ( )V [G] = 0. Applying j to this statement gives 8 < j(), 2 j(c) implies
o + -sc ( )M [j(G)] = 0. Thus by Lemma ??, since j was arbitrary, < j(), and 2 j(c)
it follows that o+ -sc ()M [j(G)] = 0, and hence o+ -sc ()V [G] 1. Thus o+ -sc ()V [G]
min{o+ -sc ()V , 1}. Thus for any which is + -supercompact, o+ -sc ()V [G] = min{o+ -sc ()V , 1}.
For the following theorem for changing Mitchell rank for supercompactness, we will again
need representing functions because I would like to now consider cases where o+ -sc ()
. Then for the most general theorem I would like to consider the cases where is ✓-
supercompact for ✓ > + . In [Hamkins2] representing functions are considered for super-
with cp(j) = and M ✓ ✓ M , then j(f )() = ↵ (this can be formalized as a first-order
statement using extenders) [Hamkins2]. Let F : Ord ! Ord. The next theorem shows how
+
to change the Mitchell rank for supercompactness for all -supercompact cardinals for
which F represents F ( ).
67
Theorem 43. For any V |= ZF C + GCH and any F : Ord ! Ord, there is a forc-
Ord-length iteration which forces at inaccessible stages to add a club c ✓ such that
inaccessible cardinal. The forcing before stage 0 is trivial, and the forcing at stage 0 adds a
club to 0. Thus the forcing P up to and including stage 0 has cardinality 0 and the forcing
past stage 0 has a dense set which is closed up to the next inaccessible cardinal. Thus P has
+
a closure point at 0, thus V ✓ V [G] satisfies the 0 approximation and cover properties by
[Hamkins4 (Lemma 13)]. Thus by [Hamkins4 (Corollary 26)], the forcing P does not create
✓-supercompact cardinals for any ✓. Note that for any ✓-supercompact cardinal , both
we will need that representing functions are still representing functions in the extension.
The fact we will use for this is from [Hamkins4] which says that if V ✓ V [G] satisfies the
hypothesis of approximation and cover theorem, then every ✓-closed embedding j : V [G] !
closed embedding). Thus, if F is a representing function for F () in the ground model,
68
(j V )(F )() = F (), and thus F is a representing function for F () with respect
The induction hypothesis is that any 0 < , where F 0 represents F (0 ) in V , has
o0+ -sc (0 )V [G] = min{o0+ -sc (0 )V , F (0 )}. Pick j : V ! M a + -supercompactness embed-
ding with critical point such that o+ -sc ()M = 0 < min{o+ -sc ()V , F ()}. We shall lift j
through P. The forcing above does not a↵ect the Mitchell rank for + -supercompactness
of since the forcing past stage has a dense subset which is closed up to the next inac-
cessible cardinal past . Call P ⇤ Q̇ the forcing up to and including stage . First we shall
an M -generic filter for j(P ). Since cp(j) = , the forcings P and j(P ) agree up to stage
. The forcing Q adds a club c ✓ such that 8 < , 2 c implies o + -sc ( )V < F ( ).
Since o + -sc ( )V < F ( ) implies o + -sc ( )M < F ( ) = j(F )( ), it follows that the th stage
of j(P ) is Q. Thus, j(P ) factors as P ⇤ Q̇ ⇤ Ptail where Ptail is the forcing past stage
. Since G ⇤ g is M -generic for P ⇤ Q̇, we only need an M [G ][g]-generic filter for Ptail
which is V [G ][g]. We will diagonalize to obtain such a filter, after checking that we have
met the criteria. Since |P | = |Q| = , and V |= GCH, it follows that the forcing P ⇤ Q̇
+
has the + -chain condition. Since M ✓ M , it follows [Hamkins1 (Theorem 54)] that
+
M [G ][g] ✓ M [G ][g]. Since |P | = , and has the + -chain condition, it has at most
<
+ +
< = + many maximal antichains. Since |j(+ )| + = ++ , it follows that Ptail
has at most ++ many maximal antichains in M [G ][g]. Since Ptail has a dense subset which
is closed up to the next inaccessible past , it has a dense subset which is + -closed. Thus,
69
we can enumerate the maximal antichains of Ptail , and build a descending sequence of condi-
tions meeting them all through the dense set which has + -closure, using this closure and
the fact that M [G ][g] is closed under + -sequences to build through the limit stages. Then
the upward closure of this sequence Gtail ✓ Ptail is M [G ][g]-generic and is in V [G ][g]. Thus
j(G ) = G ⇤ g ⇤ Gtail is M -generic, it is in V [G ][g] and j 00 G ✓ j(G ). Thus we have the
Next we lift through Q by finding an M [j(G )]-generic filter for j(Q). The forcing j(Q)
adds a club C ✓ j() such that 8 < j(), 2 C implies o + -sc ( )M [j(G )] < j(F )( ). Since
+ +
j(G ) 2 V [G ][g] and M ✓ M , it follows that M [j(G )] ✓ M [j(G )] by [Hamkins1
(Theorem 53)]. Since for every < , there is a dense subset of Q which is -closed,
it follows that there is a dense subset of j(Q) which is + -closed. Also since |Q| =
and Q has the + -chain condition, the forcing Q has at most + many maximal antichains.
<
+
Therefore j(Q) has at most |j(+ )| + = ++ many maximal antichains in M [j(G )].
Thus we can diagonalize to get a generic filter, but we will do so with a master condition as
follows. Let c = [g the new club of and consider c̄ = c [ {} which is in M [j(G )]. We
?? the Mitchell rank for supercompactness does not go up between M and M [j(G )], so
that 2 c implies o + -sc ( )M [j(G )] < F ( ) = j(F )( ). Since o+ -sc ()M [j(G)] o+ -sc ()M =
0 < min{o+ -sc ()V , F ()} it follows that o+ -sc ()M [j(G)] < F () = j(F )(). Thus c̄ is a
closed, bounded subset of j() such that every in c̄ has o + -sc ( )M [j(G )] < j(F )(). Thus
c̄ 2 j(Q). Thus diagonalize to get an M [j(G )]-generic filter g ⇤ ✓ j(Q) which contains
70
the master condition c̄. Then j 00 g ✓ j(g) = g ⇤ . Therefore we may lift the embedding to
The success of the lifting arguments for o+ -sc ()M = 0 < min{o+ -sc ()V , F ()}, where
0 was arbitrary, show that o+ -sc ()V [G] min{o+ -sc ()V , F ()}. By Lemma ?? we have
o+ -sc ()V [G] o+ -sc ()V . All that remains is to see that o+ -sc ()V [G] F (). Consider
any + -supercompact embedding j : V [G] ! M [j(G)] with critical point in V [G], and the
new club c ✓ , where 8 < , 2 c implies o + -sc ( )V < F ( ). This club is in any normal
Applying j to this statement gives 8 < j(), 2 j(c) implies o + -sc ( )M [j(G)] < j(F )( ).
Since F represents F (), we have j(F )() = F (). Since < j() and 2 j(c) it follows
that o+ -sc ()M [j(G)] < F (). Thus by Lemma ??, since j was arbitrary, o+ -sc ()V [G] F ().
Thus o+ -sc ()V [G] min{o+ -sc ()V , F ()}. Thus for any which is + -supercompact for
which F represents F () in V has o+ -sc ()V [G] = min{o+ -sc ()V , F ()}. ⇤
The most general theorem considers the case of changing Mitchell rank for ✓-supercompactness
Theorem 44. For any V |= ZF C + GCH, any ⇥ : Ord ! Ord and any F : Ord ! Ord,
F represents F () in V, and ⇥00 ✓ , then o⇥()-sc ()V [g] = min{o⇥()-sc ()V , F ()}.
71
Proof. Suppose V |= ZF C + GCH. Let ⇥ : Ord ! Ord and F : Ord ! Ord. Let P be an
Easton support Ord-length iteration which forces at to add a club c ✓ such that 2c
implies o⇥( )-sc ( )V < F ( ), whenever is a closure point of ⇥, meaning ⇥00 ✓ , otherwise
force trivially. Let G ✓ P be V -generic. Let 0 be the first inaccessible cardinal. The forcing
before stage 0 is trivial, and the forcing at stage 0 adds a club to 0. Thus the forcing P
up to and including stage 0 has cardinality 0 and the forcing past stage 0 has a dense set
which is closed up to the next inaccessible cardinal. Thus P has a closure point at 0, thus
+
V ✓ V [G] satisfies the 0 approximation and cover properties by [Hamkins4 (Lemma 13)].
Thus by Lemma ??, the forcing P does not increase Mitchell rank for ✓-supercompactness
and F represents F () in V . Here we will need that representing functions are still
representing functions in the extension. The fact we will use for this is from [Hamkins4] which
says that if V ✓ V [G] satisfies the hypothesis of approximation and cover theorem, then every
for F () in the ground model, (j V )(F )() = F (), and thus F is a representing
The induction hypothesis is that any 0 < , where ⇥00 0 ✓ 0 , and ⇥ 0 represents ⇥(),
and F 0 represents F (0 ) in V , has o⇥()-sc (0 )V [G] = min{o⇥()-sc (0 )V , F (0 )}. Pick j :
72
0 < min{o⇥()-sc ()V , F ()}. We shall lift j through P. The forcing above does not
a↵ect the Mitchell rank for ⇥()-supercompactness of since the forcing past stage has
a dense subset which is closed up to the next closure point of ⇥ past . Call P ⇤ Q̇ the
V -generic and g ✓ Q be V [G ]-generic. First, we need an M -generic filter for j(P ). Since
cp(j) = , the forcings P and j(P ) agree up to stage . The forcing Q adds a club
implies o⇥()-sc ( )M < F ( ) = j(F )( ), and j(⇥)() = ⇥(), it follows that the th stage
of j(P ) is Q. Thus, j(P ) factors as P ⇤ Q̇ ⇤ Ptail where Ptail is the forcing past stage
. Since G ⇤ g is M -generic for P ⇤ Q̇, we only need an M [G ][g]-generic filter for Ptail
which is V [G ][g]. We will diagonalize to obtain such a filter, after checking that we have
met the criteria. Since |P | = |Q| = , and V |= GCH, it follows that the forcing P ⇤ Q̇
has the + -chain condition. Since M ⇥() ✓ M , it follows [Hamkins1 (Theorem 54)] that
M [G ][g]⇥() ✓ M [G ][g]. Since |P | = , and has the + -chain condition, it has at most
+ ⇥()<
< = + many maximal antichains. Since |j(+ )| + = ⇥()+ , it follows that Ptail
has at most ⇥()+ many maximal antichains in M [G ][g]. Since Ptail has a dense subset which
is closed up to the next closure point of ⇥ past , it has a dense subset which is ⇥()-closed.
Thus, we can enumerate the maximal antichains of Ptail , and build a descending sequence
of conditions meeting them all through the dense set which has ⇥()-closure, using this
closure and the fact that M [G ][g] is closed under ⇥()-sequences to build through the limit
73
stages. Then the upward closure of this sequence Gtail ✓ Ptail is M [G ][g]-generic and is in
V [G ][g]. Thus j(G ) = G ⇤ g ⇤ Gtail is M -generic, it is in V [G ][g] and j 00 G ✓ j(G ). Thus
Next we lift through Q by finding an M [j(G )]-generic filter for j(Q). The forcing j(Q)
adds a club C ✓ j() such that 8 < j(), 2 C implies o⇥()-sc ( )M [j(G )] < j(F )( ).
Since j(G ) 2 V [G ][g] and M ⇥() ✓ M , it follows that M [j(G )]⇥() ✓ M [j(G )] by
[Hamkins1 (Theorem 53)]. Since for every < , there is a dense subset of Q which is
-closed, it follows that there is a dense subset of j(Q) which is ⇥()-closed. Also
since |Q| = and Q has the + -chain condition, the forcing Q has at most + many
⇥()<
maximal antichains. Therefore j(Q) has at most |j(+ )| + = ⇥()+ many maximal
antichains in M [j(G )]. Thus we can diagonalize to get a generic filter, but we will do so
with a master condition as follows. Let c = [g the new club of and consider c̄ = c [ {}
F ( ) = j(F )( ). Since o⇥()-sc ()M [j(G)] o⇥()-sc ()M = 0 < min{o⇥()-sc ()V , F ()}, and
j(⇥)() = ⇥() it follows that oj(⇥)()-sc ()M [j(G)] < F () = j(F )(). Thus c̄ is a closed,
bounded subset of j() such that every in c̄ has oj(⇥)()-sc ( )M [j(G )] < j(F )(). Thus
c̄ 2 j(Q). Thus diagonalize to get an M [j(G )]-generic filter g ⇤ ✓ j(Q) which contains
the master condition c̄. Then j 00 g ✓ j(g) = g ⇤ . Therefore we may lift the embedding to
The success of the lifting arguments for o⇥()-sc ()M = 0 < min{o⇥()-sc ()V , F ()},
where 0 was arbitrary, shows that o⇥()-sc ()V [G] min{o⇥()-sc ()V , F ()}. By Lemma ??
we have o⇥()-sc ()V [G] o⇥()-sc ()V . All that remains is to see that o⇥()-sc ()V [G] F ().
in V [G], and the new club c ✓ , where 8 < , 2 c implies o⇥( )-sc ( )V < F ( ).
This club is in any normal fine measure on P ⇥(). By the induction hypothesis, 8 < ,
2 c implies o⇥( )-sc ( )V [G] < F ( ). Applying j to this statement gives 8 < j(), 2 j(c)
implies oj(⇥)()-sc ( )M [j(G)] < j(F )( ). Since F represents F (), we have j(F )() =
F () and since ⇥ represents ⇥(), we have j(⇥)() = ⇥(). Since < j() and
2 j(c) it follows that o⇥()-sc ()M [j(G)] < F (). Thus by Lemma ??, since j was arbitrary,
o⇥()-sc ()V [G] F (). Thus o⇥()-sc ()V [G] min{o⇥()-sc ()V , F ()}. Thus for any which
The last theorem is about large cardinal properties close to the top. A cardinal is huge
with target if there is an elementary embedding j : V ! M , with critical point , such that
many cardinals.
Theorem 45. If is huge with target , then there is a forcing extension where is still
Hamkins and Shelah [HS], in the extension, the cardinal is not ⌘-supercompact, for all
+
⌘ > . Thus, in the extension, is not superhuge, since it is not even -supercompact,
hence not +
-huge. But, is still huge with target since the forcing is -closed. ⇤
Open Questions:
1. How high does the hierarchy of inaccessible degrees go? Can we define E0 -inaccessible?
2. If is a ⌃n+1 -reflecting cardinal, is there V [G] where is ⌃n -reflecting, but not ⌃n+1 -
reflecting?
6. Is there a forcing extension where the least strongly compact cardinal is least with
o() = 3, the second strongly compact cardinal is least above this with o() = 2 and the
third strongly compact cardinal is the least measurable above this one?
7. Is there a forcing extension where the least strongly compact cardinal is the least measur-
able, the second strongly compact cardinal is least with o() = 2, the third strongly compact
References
[Apter/Gitik] Apter/Gitik, The least measurable can be strongly compact and indestructible. The Journal of
[Easton] Easton, Powers of regular cardinals. Ann. Math. Logic 1, 139-178, MR 42 #4392, 1970.
[Gaifman] Gaifman, A generalization of Mahlo’s method for obtaining large cardinal numbers. IJM 5, 188-
200, 1967.
[Gitman] Gitman, Ramsey-like cardinals. Journal of Symbolic Logic, vol. 76, iss. 2: 519-540, 2011.
[Hamkins1] Hamkins, Forcing and Large cardinals, based on CUNY set theory lecture 2004.
[Hamkins2] Hamkins, Destruction or preservation: as you like it. Ann. Pure Appl. Logic, vol. 91, iss. 2-3,
[Hamkins3] Hamkins, Answer mathoverflow question, mathoverflow.net Forcing mildly over a worldly car-
[Hamkins4] Hamkins, Extensions with the approximation and cover properties have no new large cardinals.
[Hamkins5] Hamkins, A multiverse perpective on the axiom of constructibility Infinity and Truth, Vol. 25,
2013.
[Jech] Jech, Set Theory. Third Millenium Edition, Revised and Expanded, Springer Monographs in Mathe-
[Kan] Kanamori, The Higher Infinite. Springer Monographs in Mathematics, 2nd edition, 2003.
[Magidor] Magidor, A Study on Identity Crises. Ann. pure appl. logic, vol. 10, pp. 33-57, 1976.
77
[Mahlo] Mahlo, Uber lineare transfinite Mengen. Berichte Konig. Sachs. Ges. Wiss. Leipzig 63, 187-225,
1911.
[Mitchell] Mitchell, Hypermeasurable cardinals. In ”Logic Colloquium ’78” (M. Bo↵a et al., eds.), Mons,
Stud. Logic Foundations Math. 97, North Holland Publishing Co., Amsterdam-New York, 1979, pp.
[Schanker] Schanker, Weakly measurable cardinals. Mathematical Logic Quarterly 57 (3):266-280, 2011.
[Todorcevic] Walks on ordinals and their characteristics. Progress in Mathematics, 263. Birkhuser Verlag,