Artigo Luhmann 2
Artigo Luhmann 2
Citations:
Please note: citations are provided as a general guideline. Users should consult their preferred
citation format's style manual for proper citation formatting.
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
OPERATIONAL CLOSURE AND STRUCTURAL
COUPLING: THE DIFFERENTIATION OF
THE LEGAL SYSTEM
Niklas Luhmann *
I.
1419
1420 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 13:1419
Recalling all these attempts to avoid the fate of entropy, the the-
ory of autopoietic, self-reproducing systems does not reinvent the idea
of complete self-causation in empirical isolation. 2 This should be ob-
vious. The description of a system as autopoietic, as autonomous, as
operationally closed, refers to the network of its operations and not to
the totality of all empirical conditions, that is, the world. The ques-
tion is not how a system can maintain itself without any environmen-
tal support. Rather, it is what kind of operations enable a system to
form a self-reproducing network which relies exclusively on self-gen-
erated information and is capable of distinguishing internal needs
from what it sees as environmental problems.
The answer is no longer a disguised tautology but an obvious
one. The unity of the system is produced by the system itself.3 The
methodological task becomes to "unfold" (as logicians would say) this
tautology, and this has to be done by empirically identifying the oper-
ations which produce and reproduce the unity of the system (for ex-
ample, the biochemical processes within a living cell).
It would be easy to advance from here by distinguishing between
subjects and objects, or scientific perspectives and realities. But let us
first take another look at the question of how a system produces its
own unity. Asking "how" leads to the further question of who asks
the question; or, what are the systemic conditions of asking this ques-
tion; or simply, who is the observer? Is it the system itself or some
external unit? Perhaps it is the famous subject or simply another
system?
This technique of reflexive questioning dissolves-or should I
say, deconstructs?-the distinction between subject and object and
leaves us with the assumption of "observing systems" in the double
sense of the English -ing form.4 We ourselves may be observing sys-
tems observing observing systems; and our question remains. Are
self-maintaining, self-reproducing systems necessarily observing sys-
tems, able to distinguish themselves from their environment? How
can they maintain themselves if they cannot distinguish themselves
and what is the operational basis for this self-observation? Is the
2 Objections which focus on this point reject a theory that nobody proposes. See, e.g.,
MICHEL VAN DE KERCHOVE & FRANCOIS OST, LE SYSTtME JURIDIQUE ENTRE ORDRE ET
DtSORDRE 154-59 (1988).
3 The same tautology appears in evolutionary theories. Systems survive by adapting
themselves to their environment, and adaptation is proven by survival. The problem is the
solution because the solution is the problem. And here, too, the tautology has to be broken up
by empirically distinguishing between the internal operations that change the systems and the
resulting survival. We have to admit, therefore, the possibility that maladapted systems will
survive.
4 See HEINZ VON FOERSTER, OBSERVING SYSTEMS (1981).
1992] CLOSURE & STRUCTURAL COUPLING 1421
II.
We are now ready to start on our way through the legal system,
that is, ready to meet the first obstacle. The first surprise will be that
the famous protagonists of operational closure at the level of general
systems theory strongly reject its application to social systems. Heinz
Von Foerster finds this idea shocking; 9 nor would Humberto
Maturana and Francisco Varela join in calling social systems auto-
poietic systems. 10
Why not? The answer is easy. Not being sociologists, these au-
thors think of social systems as consisting of concrete people, individ-
uals with bodies and minds. Of course, it is impossible to admit the
closure of social systems which include the reproduction of molecules
in cells, or of cells in bodies, or of thoughts in minds, as social opera-
tions within the social system." But this mistake simply points to
unexplored possibilities of clarification. We have to be very precise in
defining the type of operation which reproduces, within a closed net-
work of its own productions, the unity of a social system. This opera-
tion can never be defined as the biochemical production of life, nor
can it be defined as the reproduction of thoughts by thoughts within
the internal darkness of a conscious system.' 2 The operation we are
looking for can only be communication.
In fact, the theory of autopoietic systems could bear the title
Taking Individuals Seriously, certainly more seriously than our hu-
manistic tradition. Taken as an individual, no human being can be
part of any other systems. Critics frequently miss this point. Arthur
Jacobson, for one, states that certainly the common law (if not the
continental law) includes "[tihe role and needs of the individual."13
But actually, the position of the individual in both versions does not
differ at all. Jacobson goes on to say that:
9 Heinz von Foerster expressed this view in the context of an interview, Gdndalogies de
l'auto-organisation, 8 CAHIERS DU CENTRE DE RECHERCHES ET D'UTUDES APPLIQUES 263
(1985).
10 See Humberto R. Maturana, Biologie der Sozialitdt, 5 DELFIN 6 (1985).
I1 Even the political reasons which make the idea unacceptable are obvious. Maturana one
day objected to the idea that a social system like Chile's under the rule of Pinochet produces
and reproduces individuals by its own structure and process.
12 Almost a Hegel citation. Hegel calls it "diefinstere Innerlichkeit des Gedankens." GE-
ORG W. F. HEGEL, Vorlesungen uber die Asthetik, in 13 WERKE 18 (1970).
13 See Arthur J. Jacobson, Autopoietic Law: The New Science of Niklas Luhmann, 87
MICH. L. REV. 1647, 1683 (1989). Compare Christophe Grzegorczyk, Systime Juridique et
Rialiti: Discussion de la Thiorie Autopoidtique du Droit, in CONTROVERSES AUTOUR DE
L'ONTOLOGIE DU DROIT 179 (Paul Amselek & Christophe Grzegorczyk eds., 1989) with the
comments of Gunther Teubner, How the Law Thinks: Toward a ConstructivistEpistemology of
Law, 23 LAW & Soc'Y REV. 727, 739-41 (1989).
19921 CLOSURE & STRUCTURAL COUPLING 1423
legal system (which, of course, does not mean that the legal system
can communicate as a collective actor on its own behalf). On the
other hand, we could hardly think of a legal system as being unable to
recognize its own boundaries, as an arbitrarily designed analytic ob-
ject of outside observers. Such a system would be unable to distin-
guish between the legal and the external consequences of a legal
decision, to mention a famous and controversial issue.2 ° It would be
unable to find reasons for staying with precedents, for distinguishing,
or for overruling. It would even be unable, as we shall see, to separate
conceptual (internal) issues and interest (external) issues. As a social
system within the societal system, it reproduces society by communi-
cation. There is no sense in separating law and society as if these were
two different objects, and not even good sense in treating the society
as the environment of the legal system. The legal system itself is an
inseparable part of the societal system-it does not simply depend on
external sources for social support and legitimation, but is an inextri-
cable part of the network that reproduces the society by recursively
connecting communication with communication. Nevertheless, the
legal system is a closed system, producing its own operations, its own
structures, and its own boundaries by its own operations; not by ac-
cepting any external determination nor, of course, any external delim-
itation whatsoever. To put it even more pointedly, just because the
legal system operates as part of the social network of societal opera-
tions, there is no sense in looking for external sources of determina-
tion and delimitation. As part of the societal system, the legal system
is a self-organizing, self-determining system. There is nothing else, no
external system that could do the job.
III.
20 See Bernard Rudden, Consequences, 24 JURID. REV. 193 (1979); Neil MacCormick, On
Legal Decisions and Their Consequences: From Dewey to Dworkin, 58 N.Y.U. L. REV. 239
(1983).
1426 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 13:1419
24 1 share some of the objections of Arthur J. Jacobson, supra note 13, against this highly
reduced formula, and the text tries to elaborate on the problems as I see them. But I would
maintain that this is not a question of explaining or organizing dynamism. Closed systems are
inherently temporalized, dynamic systems. They look for occasions, irritations, opportunities
in their environment. But even the classification as occasion, irritation, opportunity (e.g., as a
complaint) is an internal classification and not something which exists independently of the
system in its environment.
25 See NEIL MACCORMICK, LEGAL REASONING AND LEGAL THEORY (1978) (proposing
for this refined positivistic approach the brand name of "institutional theory of law").
26 See H.L.A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW (1961).
27 Even epistemology has to recognize that problems of reference should not be confused
with problems of truth and that there are no definitional links between the concepts of reality,
meaning, and truth as the Vienna circle presupposed.
1428 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 13:1419
28 This, of course, is not to say that it is simply a matter of chance. We can also recall that
some societies allow for asking the qumstio iuris even in the context of highly political issues.
The Roman republic was famous for that.
29 See Niklas Luhmann, Communication About Law in Interaction Systems, in ADVANCES
IN SOCIAL THEORY AND METHODOLOGY: TOWARD AN INTEGRATION OF MICRO- AND
MACRO-SOCIOLOGIE 234 (K. Knorr-Cetina & V. Cicourel eds., 1981).
30 At this point we meet the "historical school," and in particular, Friedrich C. von Savi-
gny, for whom a conscious formulation of legal rules is only possible when such a rule can be
found in practice. FRIEDRICH C. VON SAVIGNY, SYSTEM DES HEUTIGEN RbMISCHEN
RECHTS (SYSTEM OF MODERN ROMAN LAW) 14 (1840). We would say that the autopoietic
closure of the legal system is only possible if sufficient preadaptive advances, experiences in
handling conflicts, model cases, etc. are available. For the common law, see SIR MATTHEW
HALE, A HISTORY OF THE COMMON LAW OF ENGLAND (photo. reprint 1987)(1713)
(decoupling the question of the validity of the law and the legitimacy of the Norman conquest
as its origin).
1992] CLOSURE & STRUCTURAL COUPLING 1429
IV.
The daily problem of closed social systems is how to connect in-
ternal and external references by internal operations. At the opera-
tional level this problem is solved by distinguishing norms from facts;
that is, in terms of internal structures, distinguishing normative from
cognitive expectations. The distinction of normative and cognitive ex-
pectations, and this holds true for any distinction, has to be made; in
our case, it has to be made by the legal system. It cannot be found in
the natural or created world. It is not a "categorical" property of the
world. This means that even "facts" that are relevant for the legal
system are not facts for everybody.34 Facts are constructions, state-
ments about the world, and careful sociological investigations show
that scientific facts and facts which serve as components of legal or
31 DIG. 50.17.144 (Paulus, Ad Edictum 62) ("Not everything which is lawful is
honorable.")
32 See Neil MacCormick, Why Cases Have Rationes and What These Are, in PRECEDENT
35 See EXPERT EVIDENCE: INTERPRETING SCIENCE IN THE LAW (Roger Smith & Brian
Wynne eds., 1989) [hereinafter EXPERT EVIDENCE].
36 Brian Wynne's term. Brian Wynne, Establishingthe Rules of Laws: ConstructingExpert
Authority, in EXPERT EVIDENCE, supra note 35, at 52.
37 For a very different handling of certainty/uncertainty questions within the system of
science, see Brian L. Campbell, Uncertainty as Symbolic Action in Disputes Among Experts,
supra at 429; Susan L. Star, Scientific Work and Uncertainty, 15 Soc. STUD. OF SCi. 391
(1985).
38 Today we are well aware that this was, to a large extent, fictional history. See, e.g.,
ULRICH FALK, EIN GELEHRTER WIE WINDSCHEID: ERKUNDUNGEN AUF DEN FELDERN
DER SOGENANNTEN BEGRIFFSJURISPRUDENZ (1989).
39 See Roscoe Pound, MechanicalJurisprudence, 8 COLUM. L. REV. 605 (1908).
40 See 3 ROSCOE POUND, JURISPRUDENCE (1959). He writes: "A legal system attains the
ends of the legal order (1) by recognizing certain interests individual, public, and social; (2) by
defining the limits within which those interests shall be recognized and given effect through
legal precepts .... " Id. at 16. So some (or almost all?) interests are left without protection, or
are even repressed. This positive/negative distinction can, of course, not be deduced from the
interests as such, for even bad interests are interests. A theory which looks exclusively at
interests cannot give good reasons for this distinction except by saying that the legal system
has an interest in distinguishing protected and unprotected interests. See PHILIPP HECK,
Gesetzesauslegung und Interessenjurisprudenz (1914), reprinted in PHILIPP HECK, DAS PROB-
LEM DER RECHTSGEWINNUNG 102 (1968); BENJAMIN CARDOZO, THE NATURE OF THE JU-
19921 CLOSURE & STRUCTURAL COUPLING 1431
V.
To repeat again and again this trivial point, closure does not
mean empirical isolation. Closure is a highly selective, improbable,
artificial achievement-not in the sense of intentional design, but as
an outcome of evolution.
The emergence of closed systems requires a specific form of rela-
tions between systems and environments; it presupposes such forms
DICIAL PROCESS 112 (1921) ("One of the most fundamental interests is that the law shall be
uniform and impartial.").
41 See ANTONIO CARCATERRA, INTORNO Al BONAE FIDEI IUDICIA (1964); Yan Thomas,
La langue du droit romain: Problemes et mdthodes, 19 ARCHIVES DE PHILOSOPHIE DU DROIT
103 (1974) (asking for more refined semiotic analyses of this question).
1432 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 13:1419
44 This responds to a remark of William Evan, that the theory of autopoietic systems does
not explain how information (expectations, demands) is transmitted to the legal system. WIL-
LIAM M. EVAN, SOCIAL STRUCTURE AND LAW: THEORETICAL AND EMPIRICAL PERSPEC-
TIVES 42 (1990). There is normal communication as the operation of the societal system, to be
sure, but no contribution of external sources to what the closed system can handle as
information.
45 Francisco J. Varela, On the Conceptual Skeleton of Current Cognitive Science, in BE-
OBACHTER: KONVERGENZ DER ERKENNTNISTHEORIEN? 13 (1990), postulates a modular
(non-hierarchical) order of information processing as an additional prerequisite. See also Jo-
seph A. Goguen & Francisco J. Varela, Systems and Distinctions:Duality and Complementar-
ity, 5 INT'L J. GEN. Sys. 31 (1979).
46 It = the system, whether he or she.
1434 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 13:1419
nication reproducing society on the one hand, and special legal mean-
ings as normative projections claiming legal validity-the legal code
and the special programs (laws, regulations, contracts)-on the other.
Communication is the "domain" 4 7 in which the differentiation of a
legal system becomes possible. This does not (and cannot!) require a
communication of the legal system to the society as a relation between
sender and receiver. The legal system cannot communicate as a unity
and the society has no address. However, by operating within its own
boundary, the legal system reproduces itself and the societal system
without making this simultaneity a topic of communication, without
using it as an argument in pleading before the court, and, of course,
without needing any "legitimation" by the societal system. It hap-
pens as an unavoidable fact because (not although!) the legal system
reproduces itself under the condition of operational closure.
VI.
Given the fact of the structural coupling of the societal system
and its legal system, further structural couplings can evolve between
the legal system and other functional subsystems. All subsystems use
the same domain, "communication." 4' 8 They could not be subsystems
of the societal system on the basis of other types of operations-say
biological or conscious ones-but this does not solve all the problems
of coupling and decoupling which arise in the relations between the
subsystems. In traditional societies we find devices to represent social
order as relations between susbsystems, for example, as relations of
center and periphery, city and country; or as relations of rank be-
tween castes or estates. The transition to modem society dissolved
this order without replacing it-Foucault cites a "loss of representa-
tion" occurring in the eighteenth century.4 9 Under the regime of
functional differentiation, the societal system loses its integrative ca-
52 For the common law, see PATRICK S. ATIYAH, THE RISE AND FALL OF FREEDOM OF
CONTRACT (1979); MORTON J. HORWITZ, THE TRANSFORMATION OF AMERICAN LAW,
1780-1860 (1977); MAX RHEINSTEIN, DIE STRUKTUR DES VERTRAGLICHEN
SCHULDVERHALTNISSES IM ANGLO-AMERIKANISCHEN RECHT (1932); ALFRED W.B. SIMP-
SON, A HISTORY OF THE COMMON LAW OF CONTRACT: THE RISE OF THE ACTION OF As-
SUMPSIT (1975); EIKE VON HIPPEL, DIE KONTROLLE DER VERTRAGSFREIHEIT NACH
ANGLO-AMERIKANISCHEM RECHT: ZUGLEICH EIN BEITRAG ZUR CONSIDERATIONSLEHRE
(1963). On the continent, the nudum pactum was recognized earlier and the problem was to
reduce the amount of state intervention into contracts in the context of "mercantilistic" poli-
cies. See DIETER GRIMM, Soziale, wirtschaftliche und politische Voraussetzungen der Vertrag-
sfreiheit, in RECHT UND STAAT DER BORGERLICHEN GESELLSCHAFT 165 (1987).
53 For a more extensive treatment, see Niklas Luhmann, Verfassung als evolution/ire Er-
rungenschaft, 9 RECHTSHISTORISCHES J. 176 (1990).
54 See, e.g., CONCEPTUAL CHANGE AND THE CONSTITUTION, (Terence Ball & John G.A.
Pocock eds., 1988); POLITICAL INNOVATION AND CONCEPTUAL CHANGE (Terence Ball et al.
eds., 1989).
1992] CLOSURE & STRUCTURAL COUPLING 1437
55 For the decisive invention of the term "unconstitutional" during the eighteenth century,
see Gerald Stourzh, Constitution:Changing Meanings of the Term from the Early Seventeenth
to the Late Eighteenth Century, in CONCEPTUAL CHANGE AND THE CONSTITUTION, supra
note 54, at 35. Cf GERALD STOURZH, WEGE ZUR GRUNDRECHTSDEMOKRATIE: STUDIEN
ZUR BEGRIFFS-UND INSTITUTIONENGESCHICHTE DES LIBERALEN VERFASSUNGSTAATES
50-74 (1989).
56 For further elaboration, see NIKLAS LUHMANN, Identita't-was oder wie?, in 5 Sozio-
LOGISCHE AUFKLARUNG 14-30 (1990).
1438 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 13:1419
poietic systems are temporalized systems depending on self-generated
dynamic forms of stability, 57 they necessarily differentiate and recog-
nize their own operations by temporal orientations. Therefore, any
observer who cares for the perspective of the system itself--of course,
there can be other observers with other frames and interests--cannot
cross-identify events over boundaries.
VII.
One of the most frequent objections to the theory of autopoietic
systems in general, and its application to legal systems specifically,
states that this theory-if it is a theory at a115 8-- does not care for
empirical verification. 9 This criticism needs two comments. First,
the repertoire of empirical methods in present day sociology is very
limited and completely inadequate for objects like the legal system;
that is, self-observing objects with highly structured complexity. Re-
stricting the access to objects by available empirical methods-and I
take this denotation in its usual meaning-would simply mean not
seeing the society and its legal system as it contructs and presents
itself. It requires going out of the market and leaving the business to
others-to mass media and to sociological writers. This should not be
the last word. Secondly, one can look for new combinations of (1)
well-known and uncontroversial (maybe obvious or even trivial) facts;
and (2) theoretical descriptions which present the obvious in unusual
illumination. The distinction between operational closure and struc-
tural coupling is one of these theoretical instruments. In other words,
given the structure of its domain, sociology cannot reduce its concept
of social reality to self-created data. We may even doubt whether
there is any correlation between empirical research and social reality,
except by the methodologically unguided "active interpretation" of
results.
If these considerations suggest (to repeat, for the present situa-
tion) a primacy of refined theoretical research, they do not exclude
57 It is a frequent, but very crude and uninformed, error to say that the theory of auto-
poietic systems does not have the possibility of taking dynamism (on the level of operations)
and change (on the level of structures) into account. On the contrary, the theory has no place
for any kind of non-dynamic, unchangeable, "essential," "substantive" components.
58 Within the context of American sociology, this level of theorizing is sometimes called
"metatheoretical"-as in the section title under which a paper of the present author is printed,
in DIFFERENTIATION THEORY AND SOCIAL CHANGE: COMPARATIVE AND HISTORICAL PER-
SPECTIVES (Jeffrey C. Alexander & Paul Colomy eds., 1990). Seen from a European perspec-
tive, this reflects the rather modest level of theoretical aspirations in present day American
sociology. Cf DAG OSTERBERG, METASOCIOLOGY: AN INQUIRY INTO THE ORIGINS AND
VALIDITY OF SOCIAL THOUGHT (1988).
59 See, e.g., EVAN, supra note 44, at 46.
1992] CLOSURE & STRUCTURAL COUPLING 1439
VIII.
Finally, I return to the concept of operational closure. Focussing
on the operation that autopoietically reproduces the system as the net-
work which reproduces its operations offers new insights with respect
to the relation of structure and process. An autopoietic system does
not consist of two different kinds of entities, namely structures and
processes. It is not composed of two different kinds of matter or sub-
stance. The enzymes of the living cell are at the same time outcomes
of production, productive factors, and programming factors which or-
ganize the reproduction of the cell. The human mind does not consist
of two different kinds of entities which have been called-by the
Logic of Port Royal62 and by Locke, 63 as well as their followers-
ideas and representations. There are not two different qualities of a
communicative system, langue and parole, as the linguistic theory of
Saussure would have it.6M Finally, it is questionable what it means to
60 See Niklas Luhmann, The Third Question: The Creative Use of Paradoxesin Law and
Legal History, 15 J. L. & Soc'y 153 (1988).
61 See, e.g., MICHAEL HUTER, DIE PRODUKTION VON RECHT: EINE SELBSTREFEREN-
TIELLE THEORIE DER WIRTSCHAFT, ANGEWANDT AUF DEN FALL DES ARZNEIMIT-
TELPATENTRECHTS (1989).
62 ANTOINE ARNAULD & PIERRE NICOLE, LA LOGIQUE OU L'ART DE PENSER (1972)
(1662).
63 See JOHN LOCKE, AN ESSAY CONCERNING HUMAN UNDERSTANDING (Peter H. Nid-
ditch ed., 1975).
64 See F. DE SAUSSURE, supra note 5.
1440 CARDOZO LAW REVIEW [Vol. 13:1419
say that a legal system consists of "norms and activities. ' 65 Rather,
the system uses the same type of operation-be it biochemical replica-
tion, thought, or communication-in the dual function of (1) produc-
ing subsequent operations; and (2) confirming or changing the
structure used to select the next operation. In the sense of Heinz Von
Foerster, it is a non-trivial, self-referential machine-a machine that
uses every operation to construct itself anew.66 As observers, and for
analytic purposes, we may distinguish these two functions of produc-
ing operations and using, confirming, or changing structures. In real-
ity, these are only two aspects which necessarily require each other.
In a complex system you cannot fix the next operation without select-
ing it, you cannot select without narrowing the choice in the first
place, and you cannot restrict the possibilities at hand without ac-
cepting frames, as some people say, or structures, or in the case of
social and legal systems, expectations.
Operational closure, then, means that a system has to rely on all-
purpose operations of a specific type (and, of course, not anything
goes!). It has to use the same type of operation for confirming and
changing (or simply forgetting) structures, and each operation is al-
ways determining the next operation. It is simply a prime fact that
the autopoiesis goes on and on. There is no operation available that
could stop it, because all operations gain their own unity by produc-
ing subsequent operations. The system may select, condense, confirm,
change, or forget structures-but all this is a way to continue its own
autopoiesis. Of course, this does not prevent destruction, but it goes
on as long as it goes on. If a system can organize structural changes,
it can increase its adaptive capacity, but also its maladaption. Under
a condition of sufficient complexity, a system can differentiate proce-
dures for changing structures, and structures for organizing proce-
dures for changing structures. This all requires and uses the type of
operation that produces and reproduces the unity of the system.
I conclude with a trivial remark: There is no conservative bias in
such a theory. The system has no preference for maintaining itself,
there is simply no choice. It can continue by confirming or by chang-
ing its structure if operations are available to focus on such an out-
come; otherwise it just happens. An observer (which may be the
ORETISCHE EINFHRUNG IN DIE RECHTSTHEORIE 41 (1988). I suppose that most legal theo-
rists would tend to accept this without giving further thought to what it could mean to say
"and"-norms and activities.
66 See Heinz Von Foerster, Principles of Self-Organization-In a Socio-Managerial Con-
text, in SELF-ORGANIZATION AND MANAGEMENT OF SOCIAL SYSTEMS: INSIGHTS,
PROMISES, DOUBTS, AND QUESTIONS 2, 8-10 (Hans Ulrich & Gilbert J.B. Probst eds., 1984).
1992] CLOSURE & STRUCTURAL COUPLING 1441
system itself) may or may not discover that structures have changed
over time. He may see that intentional changes are conservative with
respect to the frames, values, procedures, and constitutions which are
needed for, and confirmed by, intentional changes. An observer may
use the distinction of static and dynamic systems for himself. Systems
theory, however, will advise him that this scheme is a crude simplifi-
cation. Autopoietic systems are systems organizing dynamic stability.
If an observer does not heed to this advice, and his own autopoiesis
does not force him to do so, it would be advisable to change the topic
of interest and observe the observer.